- Published: December 10, 2021
- Updated: December 17, 2021
- University / College: Queen's University Belfast
- Language: English
- Downloads: 12
Too Much Neural Reuse, Even for a Metaphorical Brain
Conceptual mappings are correspondances between conceptual domains ( SPACE , TIME , FORCE , EMOTION , etc.) or between entities within the same conceptual domain. Through mapping, we project inferences, elements, and relations from one mental configuration to another. Sets of mappings can become entrenched, creating powerful cognitive habits. For example, across many cultures around the world, temporal relations are conceived by means of spatial relations, in language (“ Saturday is almost here”), artifacts (timelines, calendars, sundials), or gesture ( Núñez and Sweetser, 2006 ). Some of the mappings for this template are: duration is spatial extent, events are landmarks, or time is motion along a path.
From over 30 years of conceptual mappings research emerges a picture of the conceptual system as a set of mapping habits. Instead of a static repository of concepts, we have a dynamic network connecting mental structures. Mapping is not exceptional: it is the norm. It is through mapping that concepts are formed, learned, and developed creatively. These ideas have boosted the interest in the most remarkable manifestations of mapping in language and thought: metaphor, metonymy, analogy, counterfactuals, etc.
Metaphor has received far more attention than all the other phenomena combined. Researchers in Conceptual Metaphor Theory (CMT) ( Lakoff and Johnson, 1980 ; Lakoff, 1993 ), have identified many sets of cross-domain mappings underlying conventional metaphorical expressions: TIME IS SPACE , LIFE IS A JOURNEY , ANGER IS HEAT , EVENTS ARE ACTIONS , etc. According to CMT, conceptual metaphors are static, ontological, fixed sets of partial correspondances between two conceptual domains. Metaphor transfers inferences from the source domain, more concrete or better structured, to the target domain, which is more abstract or less delineated. A system of thousands of metaphorical mappings constitutes the main mechanism for abstract thought in the human mind.
From the nineties, the semantic postulates of CMT have been used to develop the Neural Theory of Language (NTL) ( Gallese and Lakoff, 2005 ; Feldman, 2008 ; Lakoff, 2008 ). In NTL, conceptual metaphors are replaced by neural mappings, combinations of simple neural circuits that carry out conceptual mappings. The major function of all this neural binding is the reuse of sensorimotor brain mechanisms for new roles in language and reasoning. This is congenial with the grounding of abstract concepts in perceptual experience ( Barsalou, 1999 , 2008 ), called embodiment in conceptual mappings research ( Johnson, 1987 , 2008 ; Lakoff, 1987 ; Lakoff and Johnson, 1999 ). The overarching idea of CMT-NTL is a “ metaphorical mind-brain,” based on direct, binary transfer across domains. The transfer is carried out through static cognitive habits, which are implemented by neural circuitry connecting pairs of brain areas. For the brain, metaphor is once more privileged over all other manifestations of mapping, just like it was for the mind. A good example of the rapidly growing interest in the neuroscience of metaphor is the Frontiers issue about the topic, currently being edited by Vicky T. Lai and Seana Coulson.
But the metaphorical brain seems quite insufficient to account for the pervasiveness and complexity of neural reuse. In a recent BBS target article, Michael Anderson (2010) shows that what is going on in the brain dwarfs the predictions of embodiment or CMT-NTL. Statistics run on thousands of fMRI studies indicate that even fairly small brain regions are typically reused in multiple tasks, with even higher reuse probabilities if a region is involved in perception or action ( Anderson et al., 2010 ).
Neural reuse is ubiquitous and dynamic, and many of its results cannot be explained as domain-structuring inheritance. Anderson examines, among others, the following examples: the SNARC effect (a mental number line with magnitudes increasing from left to right), the correlation between finger representation and numerical cognition, the interaction of word and gesture, or the phonological loop in working memory. These cases present no metaphorical projection, and some of them involve more than two components. Rather than direct transfer of information, a given system seems to be reused for a non-primary purpose because it happens to have a function or structure that are appropriate for the particular cognitive task at hand. As Anderson claims, we need a broader theoretical framework, able to account for those individual phenomena as well as for the general prevalence of neural reuse.
From Transfer to Emergence: The Network Model of Conceptual Integration
Can conceptual mappings research provide such a framework? For one thing, the CMT-NTL model is certainly not the only one in the field. CMT and the pervasiveness of mapping were the point of departure of Gilles Fauconnier’s Mental Space Theory ( Fauconnier, 1985 , 1997 ), later developed by Fauconnier and Mark Turner into Conceptual Integration Theory, or Blending Theory (BT) ( Turner, 1996 , 2014 ; Fauconnier and Turner, 2002 ).
Beyond the common ground with CMT ( Fauconnier and Lakoff, 2013 ), BT introduces significant innovations. Mental spaces are not vast domains such as TIME or SPACE , but small conceptual packets that flexibly combine entrenched structures and contextual information, for local purposes of thought and action. Mappings are established through structural or functional correspondances between input spaces in a generic mental space. The participation of more than two inputs is quite typical. Selectively projected to a blended space or conceptual blend , elements from the inputs interact, typically producing emergent structure, which cannot be accounted for by direct transfer between domains. Inferences can take place in the blend, but also be projected back to the inputs, which can be modified as the process unfolds. The mappings, the emergence of novel structure, the adjustment of the inputs, and everything else going on is guided by universal governing principles and competing optimality principles, by the functional requirements of the particular network of mental spaces, dictated by context and goals, and by the creativity of the individual or group who are striving to make the most of it all.
The overarching picture that results from BT bears important differences with that of CMT-NTL. Advanced blending underlies all manifestations of mapping, including metaphor, which is just one more surface product of this species-defining capacity for integrating disparate mental components into new, meaningful wholes. The human brain is a bubble chamber of mental spaces, constantly building new integration networks, and a culture is an even larger bubble chamber ( Fauconnier and Turner, 2002 , p. 321–322). Just like evolution—and neural reuse—, blending is opportunistic: it reuses whatever is functionally suitable, right there and then. As it happens with the natural selection of living organisms, the process of trial and error in conceptual and neural reuse never stops. Through it, minds and cultures select the few integrations that are really useful, anchor them by means of symbolic procedures, and pass them on to the next generation. To become productive habits, both generic templates of conceptual integration and patterns of neural reuse need to find an adequate niche within the general system (about the notion of neural niche , see: Anderson, 2010 , and the commentary by Atsushi Iriki therein; Iriki and Sakura, 2008 ; Iriki and Taoka, 2012 ).
One Example: Opportunistic Reuse in the Number Line and the Timeline
In blending as in neural reuse, a given item, once identified as potentially useful, is integrated into the network under construction. If necessary and possible, the item is adjusted for optimization in its new function. If it works, the item is kept in the network, although it still remains available for its older functions. Networks and their components are discarded and entrenched in a dynamic, extremely agile process. What is going on here is not direct transfer of structure, but rather the construction of a new whole with old pieces. The novel properties are not borrowed from the structures being reused, but result from their performance in a new network.
Among other examples, Anderson (2010) illustrates this with the spatial-numerical association of response codes (SNARC) effect, that is, a mental number line in which numerals are arrayed from left to right, in order of increasing magnitude ( Dehaene et al., 1993 ). As Anderson explains, there is no metaphoric mapping or perceptual grounding here: in sensorimotor experience, magnitude may increase with height (the MORE IS UP metaphor), but not laterally, and certainly not in the direction of writing. Numerals do not inherit the structure of the spatial shifting mechanism: the left-to-right line has been picked opportunistically, and integrated with numeral magnitude, simply because the resulting blend meets the requirements of the task. We could add to Anderson’s argument by pointing out that the mental number line, as a symbolic device, needed considerable cultural time to emerge: it was only invented in seventeenth-century Europe, although awareness of potential correspondances between numbers and spatial relations dates back to Babylon ( Núñez, 2009 ). It took thousands of years for the pattern to find an appropriate niche, alongside a representational format that would ensure its transmission.
The number line is what gets called a material anchor for a conceptual blend ( Hutchins, 2005 ). A perceptual structure is used as an input in the integration process. In the blend, perceptual relations are fused with conceptual relations. Now consider a very similar case. Varied psycholinguistic evidence shows that processing temporal expressions causes the automatic activation of a mental timeline, also running from left to right in cultures with that writing system ( Torralbo et al., 2006 ; Weger and Pratt, 2008 ; Santiago et al., 2010 ). Blending theorists have revised the TIME IS SPACE metaphor, and shown that it is a complex network that produces a motion scene with special rules and constraints, designed to facilitate the representation of time: all observers are on the same spot, all objects move along the same path, and spatial relations can even be modified by the emotional attitude of the observer: “ Monday is almost here, but Friday is so far away” ( Fauconnier and Turner, 2008 ). The straight line is particularly useful for anchoring this blended scene. The result is a graphic representation with novel properties, which allow us to see diachrony at a glance, to divide it easily into periods, to represent events as dots, etc.
The timeline is a generic integration template that blends at least four inputs: time and time measures, spatial extent, objects, and events ( Coulson and Cánovas, 2013 ). Spatial shifting from left to right is absent from all these components, but it happens to facilitate the task immensely, and thus it is imported to the blend, for local purposes. The pattern is not functional as a metaphor in language, where past and future are not on the left or right, but it is extremely productive in gesture ( Casasanto and Jasmin, 2012 ), where the lateral axis is more easily available. Again, the timeline has a long history of failed cultural representations behind it ( Rosenberg and Grafton, 2010 ), but, once the blending template found its niche, it is reused time and again, and can even be adapted for representing complex emotions and creating sophisticated poetic effects ( Cánovas and Jensen, 2013 ). Metaphor is useful, but not enough to understand the timeline: a broader framework of reuse and integration is needed.
What Kind of Model We Need
BT researchers have indeed identified many recurrent patterns and theorized about them, but we still lack a general framework for generic integration templates (some work along those lines: Fauconnier and Turner, 2002 ; Fauconnier, 2009 ; Cánovas, 2010 , 2011 ; Turner, 2014 ). A fruitful interaction with research on neural reuse can impose further constraints and requisites than those observed in the semantic or semiotic analyses. A model of conceptual mapping habits fully compatible with neural reuse may include the following:
• Network thinking ( Mitchell, 2006 ) rather than direct binary transfer.
• Flexibility in the activation, selection, and integration of conceptual and neural patterns.
• Focus on emergence.
• Emphasis on competing optimality principles, e. g., a left-to-right straight line leaves aside many relevant aspects of time or magnitude, but its functionality is privileged.
• Detailed examination of how context and goals, including cultural diachrony, shape the process of integration.
• A model of entrenchment not based on ontological projection, but on the idea of “ attaining a niche” through instance-based learning and context-sensitive usage.
Conflict of Interest Statement
The authors declare that the research was conducted in the absence of any commercial or financial relationships that could be construed as a potential conflict of interest.
References
Anderson, M. L. (2010). Neural reuse: a fundamental organizational principle of the brain michael. Behav. Brain Sci . 33, 1–69. doi: 10. 1017/S0140525X10000853
Pubmed Abstract | Pubmed Full Text | CrossRef Full Text
Anderson, M. L., Brumbaugh, J., and Aysu Şuben, A. (2010). “ Investigating functional cooperation in the human brain using simple graph-theoretic methods,” in Computational Neuroscience , (Springer) 31–42. doi: 10. 1007/978-0-387-88630-5_2. Available online at: http://link. springer. com/chapter/10. 1007/978-0-387-88630-5_2
Barsalou, L. W. (1999). Perceptual symbol systems. Behav. Brain Sci . 22, 577–660. doi: 10. 1017/S0140525X99002149
Pubmed Abstract | Pubmed Full Text | CrossRef Full Text
Barsalou, L. W. (2008). Grounded cognition. Annu. Rev. Psychol . 59, 617–645. doi: 10. 1146/annurev. psych. 59. 103006. 093639
Pubmed Abstract | Pubmed Full Text | CrossRef Full Text
Cánovas, C. P. (2010). Erotic emissions in greek poetry: a generic integration network. Cogn. Semiotics 6, 7–32. doi: 10. 3726/81610_7
Cánovas, C. P. (2011). The genesis of the arrows of love: diachronic conceptual integration in greek mythology. Am. J. Philol . 132, 553–579. doi: 10. 1353/ajp. 2011. 0044
Cánovas, C. P., and Jensen, M. F. (2013). Anchoring time-space mappings and their emotions: the timeline blend in poetic metaphors. Lang. Lit . 22, 45–59. doi: 10. 1177/0963947012469751
Casasanto, D., and Jasmin, K. (2012). The Hands of Time: Temporal Gestures in English Speakers . Available online at://www. degruyter. com/view/j/cog. 2012. 23. issue-4/cog-2012-0020/cog-2012-0020/cog-2012-0020. xml
Coulson, S., and Cánovas, C. P. (2013). Understanding timelines. J. Cogn. Semiotics 5, 198–219. doi: 10. 1515/cogsem. 2013. 5. 12. 198
Dehaene, S., Bossini, S., and Giraux, P. (1993). The mental representation of parity and number magnitude. J. Exp. Psychol. Gen . 122, 371–396. doi: 10. 1037/0096-3445. 122. 3. 371
Fauconnier, G. (1985). Mental Spaces: Aspects of Meaning Construction in Natural Language . Cambridge, MA: Cambridge University Press.
Fauconnier, G. (1997). Mappings in Thought and Language . Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. doi: 10. 1017/CBO978113914220
Fauconnier, G. (2009). Generalized integration networks. New Dir. Cogn. Linguist . 147–160.
Pubmed Abstract | Pubmed Full Text
Fauconnier, G., and Lakoff, G. (2013). On metaphor and blending. Cogn. Semiotics 5, 393–399.
Fauconnier, G., and Turner, M. (2002). The Way We Think: Conceptual Blending and the Mind’s Hidden Complexities . New York, NY: Basic Books.
Fauconnier, G., and Turner, M. (2008). “ Rethinking metaphor,” in The Cambridge Handbook of Metaphor and Thought , ed R. W Gibbs (Cambridge, MA: Cambridge University Press), 57–66. doi: 10. 1017/CBO9780511816802. 005
Feldman, J. A. (2008). From Molecule to Metaphor: A Neural Theory of Language . Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
Gallese, V., and Lakoff, G. (2005). The brain’s concepts: the role of the sensory-motor system in conceptual knowledge. Cogn. Neuropsychol . 22, 455–479. doi: 10. 1080/02643290442000310
Pubmed Abstract | Pubmed Full Text | CrossRef Full Text
Hutchins, E. (2005). Material anchors for conceptual blends. J. Pragmatics 37, 1555–1577. doi: 10. 1016/j. pragma. 2004. 06. 008
Iriki, A., and Sakura, O. (2008). The neuroscience of primate intellectual evolution: natural selection and passive and intentional niche construction. Philos. Trans. R. Soc. B Biol. Sci . 363, 2229–2241. doi: 10. 1098/rstb. 2008. 2274
Pubmed Abstract | Pubmed Full Text | CrossRef Full Text
Iriki, A., and Taoka, M. (2012). Triadic (ecological, Neural, Cognitive) niche construction: a scenario of human brain evolution extrapolating tool use and language from the control of reaching actions. Philos. Trans. R. Soc. B Biol. Sci . 367, 10–23. doi: 10. 1098/rstb. 2011. 0190
Pubmed Abstract | Pubmed Full Text | CrossRef Full Text
Johnson, M. (1987). The Body in the Mind: The Bodily Basis of Meaning, Imagination, and Reason . Chicago, IL: University Of Chicago Press.
Johnson, M. (2008). The Meaning of the Body: Aesthetics of Human Understanding . Reprint. Chicago, IL: University Of Chicago Press.
Lakoff, G. (1987). Women, Fire, and Dangerous Things . 1997th Edn. Chicago, IL: University Of Chicago Press.
Lakoff, G. (1993). “ The contemporary theory of metaphor.” in Metaphor and Thought , ed A. Ortony (Cambridge, CA: Cambridge University Press). doi: 10. 1017/CBO9781139173865. 013
Lakoff, G. (2008). “ The neural theory of metaphor.” in The Cambridge Handbook of Metaphor and Thought , ed R. W Gibbs, Jr (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press), 17–38. doi: 10. 1017/CBO9780511816802. 003
Lakoff, G., and Johnson, M. (1980). Metaphors We Live By . Chicago, IL: University Of Chicago Press.
Lakoff, G., and Johnson, M. (1999). Philosophy in the Flesh: The Embodied Mind and Its Challenge to Western Thought . New York, NY: Basic Books.
Mitchell, M. (2006). Complex systems: network thinking. Artif. Intell . 170, 1194–1212. doi: 10. 1016/j. artint. 2006. 10. 002
Núñez, R. (2009). Numbers and arithmetic: neither hardwired nor out there. Biol. Theory 4, 68–83. doi: 10. 1162/biot. 2009. 4. 1. 68
Núñez, R. E., and Sweetser, E. (2006). With the future behind them: convergent evidence from aymara language and gesture in the crosslinguistic comparison of spatial construals of time. Cogn. Sci . 30, 401–450. doi: 10. 1207/s15516709cog0000_62
Pubmed Abstract | Pubmed Full Text | CrossRef Full Text
Rosenberg, D., and Grafton, A. (2010). Cartographies of Time: A History of the Timeline . New York, NY: Princeton Architectural Press.
Santiago, J., Román, A., Ouellet, M., Rodríguez, N., and Pérez-Azor, P. (2010). In hindsight, life flows from left to right. Psychol. Res . 74, 59–70. doi: 10. 1007/s00426-008-0220-0
Pubmed Abstract | Pubmed Full Text | CrossRef Full Text
Torralbo, A., Santiago, J., and Lupiáñez, J. (2006). Flexible conceptual projection of time onto spatial frames of reference. Cogn. Sci . 30, 745–757. doi: 10. 1207/s15516709cog0000_67
Pubmed Abstract | Pubmed Full Text | CrossRef Full Text
Turner, M. (1996). The Literary Mind: The Origins of Thought and Language . New York, NY: Oxford University Press.
Turner, M. (2014). The Origin of Ideas: Blending, Creativity, and the Human Spark . New York, NY: Oxford University Press.
Weger, U. W., and Pratt, J. (2008). Time flies like an arrow: space-time compatibility effects suggest the use of a mental timeline. Psychon. Bull. Rev . 15, 426–430. doi: 10. 3758/PBR. 15. 2. 426