1,807
26
Essay, 7 pages (1700 words)

A commentary on theory of mind

The Child as Philosopher

“ You don’t know what I’m thinking,” my 3-year-old granddaughter called to me from her car seat. Her out of-the-blue, metacognitive comment confirmed that, despite inconsistent performance on false belief tasks, young children reveal sophisticated mindreading abilities in their spontaneous talk ( Shatz, 1994 ). At the least, she was concerned with knowledge in another’s mind. But her statement suggested more: With no prior conversational context, and serving no communicative or behavioral purpose, it seemed to be in the tradition of philosophy of mind. What kind of theory of mind (TOM) lay behind it?

Possible Theories of Mind

As scientists, we must consider the most economical, reasonable explanations for behavior. Possibly, a minimal TOM, e. g., behavior-reading as clues to intention ( Butterfill and Apperly, 2013 ), could have accounted for her comment. Because I was driving and directing my gaze elsewhere while she sat quietly, she probably knew that I lacked perceptual information about her. (Behavior-reading handles well the findings on animal “ mindreading,” Lurz, 2011 ). However, comments about mindreading from competent language users like her may exemplify more, namely, thinking about mind. Possibly she held “ the doctrine of opacity of others’ minds,” the belief that it is near impossible to know what another is thinking ( Robbins and Rumsey, 2008 ).

In numerous Melanesian cultures, talk about others’ thoughts is inappropriate, but evidence is lacking that mindreading does not happen (see Keane, 2008 ). Thus, the universality of mindreading among human adults has not been seriously challenged. Indeed, discoveries with pre-linguistic infants and animals have encouraged the view that, while possibly necessary for mature mindreading, language is very likely subsequent to early TOM skills (e. g., Malle, 2002 ). Apparently, children in Melanesian cultures still read others’ minds, but they must learn not to talk about them ( Schieffelin, 2008 ).

In Western cultures, social experience and family talk about mental states fosters TOM development (see Antonietti et al., 2006 ). As the younger sibling in an upper-middle class American family, my granddaughter very likely heard much talk about mental states and so would have been unrestrained in talking about our minds. Still, one cannot know for sure whether she held a TOM based on behavioral clues or on impossible access.

To explain improving performance with age, TOM theorists have proposed various mechanisms such as a mindreading “ module” with performance constraints, growing representational ability, or social experience and language skill. Nichols and Stich (2003) even proposed a multi-component theory drawing on previous accounts. These authors’ efforts, as well as later ones, show that no single mechanism explains all the findings on different-aged humans and animals. The answer to the question of who can read minds, when and how, is not simple.

What is Mindreading?

At the least, mindreading entails entity A assessing an internal mental state of entity B that is not accessible from direct perception. Hence, inference on the part of A is necessary. (See Premack and Woodruff, 1979 ; They coined the term, TOM.) Being a good reader of others’ behaviors apparently is insufficient for “ full-blown” TOM ( Butterfill and Apperly, 2013 ). Mature mindreading is not constrained to a single (e. g., competitive) circumstance. To account for mindreading-like behaviors in animals and pre-linguistic infants while not granting them mature TOMs, researchers have proposed various minimal or two-system theories (e. g., Apperly and Butterfill, 2009 ; Ruffman, 2014 ). Already their proposals have garnered a variety of criticisms (e. g., Carruthers, 2014 ; Scott, 2014 ).

So, years after my granddaughter’s remark, and after studying many recent arguments, I cannot definitively answer the question of what kind of theory she had. Lurz et al. (2014) propose “ optimistic agnosticism” to address whether animals behavior-read or mind-read, but I am not as optimistic as they that further experimentation will establish the truth for either animals or young children. Lurz et al. say that the evidence already favors an innate module, even in animals, as the basis for TOM. The notion of modularity comes from Fodor’s (1983) proposal of it as the mind’s organizing principle. His work follows from the idea of an innate human language capacity ( Chomsky, 1965 ).

The language and TOM modules are similar in that both have some innate bases or other, and both require environmental input to achieve mature status, that is, “ full-blown” TOM and specific language competence. Nonetheless, the modules and their developmental constraints are critically different. The innate language module constrains syntax, allowing humans to use limited data to develop a specific syntactic system. Thus, the syntax module accounts for various features of a language being packaged together so that when a crucial piece of data is encountered, those multiple features can be acquired simultaneously. In contrast, the mindreading module seems to consist of a score of disparate, (albeit possibly innate) abilities functioning together to produce early TOM-like behavior. As these skills grow, so TOM ability grows, bringing success on increasingly difficult tasks. Animal modularity may be different from human modularity altogether, with entirely different constraints (e. g., limited to competitive contexts; Barrett and Kurzban, 2006 ). More clarity on the nature of TOM modules is needed to decide which, if any, modules share more than an ill-defined label.

The problem of clarity plagues other constructs in TOM proposals as well. For example, the question of what they represent when creatures mind-read is a conundrum because there is no clear definition of representation. Without clear basic constructs, there can be no determinative testing of modular or any other TOM theories.

Only human children can acquire both false-belief understanding and syntactic language. Several researchers have proposed that language is the human ability that can integrate early skills, leading to more advanced ones, (e. g., Spelke, 2003 ; Shatz, 2007 ). Or, humans may have a higher-order cognitive capacity that accounts for both language and “ full-blown” TOM (see Penn et al., 2008 ; Shatz, 2008 ). Such proposals may be agnostic with regard to whether animals’ abilities are the evolutionary precursors to adult human strengths, but they are not so with regard to the “ pro-discontinuity” position that humans are basically different from animals.

When my 3-year-old granddaughter said, “ You don’t know what I’m thinking,” my first and lasting impression was that she had marked a crucial difference between us. The grandmother in me credited her with a rather mature TOM. Although, my scientist’s head may be more agnostic, it is not at odds with my grandmother’s heart. I believe, even after perusing the last decade’s work, that young humans have different TOMs from animals. Proof awaits.

Conflict of Interest Statement

The author declares that the research was conducted in the absence of any commercial or financial relationships that could be construed as a potential conflict of interest.

References

Antonietti, A., Liverta-Sempio, O., Marchetti, A., and Astington, J. W. (2006). “ Mental language and understanding of epistemic and emotional mental states: contextual aspects,” in Theory of Mind and Language in Developmental Contexts , eds A. Antonietti, O. Liverta-Sempio and A. Marchetti (Dordecht: Springer), 1–30.

Apperly, I. A., and Butterfill, S. A. (2009). Do humans have two systems to track beliefs and belief-like states? Psychol. Rev. 116, 953–970. doi: 10. 1037/a0016923

Barrett, H. C., and Kurzban, R. (2006). Modularity in cognition: framing the debate. Psychol. Rev. 113, 628–647. doi: 10. 1037/0033-295X. 113. 3. 628

Butterfill, S. A., and Apperly, I. A. (2013). How to construct a minimal theory of mind. Mind Lang. 28, 606–637. doi: 10. 1111/mila. 12036

Carruthers, P. (2014). Two systems for mindreading? Rev. Philos. Psychol . doi: 10. 1007/s13164-015-0259-y. [Epub ahead of print].

Chomsky, N. (1965). Aspects of a Theory of Syntax. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

Fodor, J. A. (1983). The Modularity of Mind . Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

Keane, W. (2008). Others, other minds, and others’ theories of mind: an afterword on the psychology and politics of opacity claims. Anthropol. Q. 81, 473–482. doi: 10. 1353/anq. 0. 0000

Lurz, R. W., Kanet, S., and Krachun. (2014). Animal mindreading: a defense of optimistic agnosticism. Mind Lang. 29, 428–454. doi: 10. 1111/mila. 12058

Lurz, R. W. (2011). Mindreading Animals: The Debate Over What Animals Know About Other Minds . Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

Malle, B. F. (2002). “ The relation between language and theory of mind development and evolution,” in The Evolution of Language and Pre-language , eds T. Givon and B. F. Malle (Amsterdam: Benjamins), 265–285.

Nichols, S., and Stich, S. P. (2003). Mindreading. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

Penn, D. C., Holyoak, K. J., and Povinelli, D. J. (2008). Darwin’s mistake: explaining the discontinuity between human and nonhuman minds. Behav. Brain Sci. 31, 109–138. doi: 10. 1017/S0140525X08003543

Premack, D., and Woodruff, G. (1979). Does the chimpanzee have a theory of mind? Behav. Brain Sci. 1, 515–516.

Robbins, J., and Rumsey, A. (2008). Introduction: cultural anthropology and the opacity of other minds. Anthropol. Q. 81, 407–420. doi: 10. 1353/anq. 0. 0005

Ruffman, T. (2014). To belief or not belief: children’s theory of mind. Dev. Rev. 34, 265–293. doi: 10. 1016/j. dr. 2014. 04. 001

Schieffelin, B. B. (2008). Speaking only your own mind: reflections on talk, gossip and intentionality in Bosavi (PNG). Anthropol. Q. 81, 431–441. doi: 10. 1353/anq. 0. 0003

Scott, R. M. (2014). Post hoc versus predictive accounts of children’s theory of mind: a reply to Ruffman. Dev. Rev. 34, 300–304. doi: 10. 1016/j. dr. 2014. 05. 001

Shatz, M. (1994). A Toddler’s Life: Becoming a Person . New York, NY: Oxford University Press.

Shatz, M. (2007). “ Revisiting A Toddler’s Life for The Toddler Years : conversational participation as a tool for learning across knowledge domains,” in Socioemotional Development in the Toddler Years , eds C. A. Brownell and C. B. Kopp (New York, NY: Guilford), 241–257.

Shatz, M. (2008). Language as a consequence and an enabler of the exercise of higher-order relational capabilities: evidence from toddlers. Behav. Brain Sci. 31, 145–146. doi: 10. 1017/S0140525X08003713

Spelke, E. (2003). “ What makes us smart? Core knowledge and natural language,” in Language in Mind , eds D. Gentner and S. Goldin-Meadow (Cambridge, MA: MIT Press), 277–311.

Thank's for Your Vote!
A commentary on theory of mind. Page 1
A commentary on theory of mind. Page 2
A commentary on theory of mind. Page 3
A commentary on theory of mind. Page 4
A commentary on theory of mind. Page 5
A commentary on theory of mind. Page 6
A commentary on theory of mind. Page 7
A commentary on theory of mind. Page 8
A commentary on theory of mind. Page 9

This work, titled "A commentary on theory of mind" was written and willingly shared by a fellow student. This sample can be utilized as a research and reference resource to aid in the writing of your own work. Any use of the work that does not include an appropriate citation is banned.

If you are the owner of this work and don’t want it to be published on AssignBuster, request its removal.

Request Removal
Cite this Essay

References

AssignBuster. (2022) 'A commentary on theory of mind'. 26 July.

Reference

AssignBuster. (2022, July 26). A commentary on theory of mind. Retrieved from https://assignbuster.com/a-commentary-on-theory-of-mind/

References

AssignBuster. 2022. "A commentary on theory of mind." July 26, 2022. https://assignbuster.com/a-commentary-on-theory-of-mind/.

1. AssignBuster. "A commentary on theory of mind." July 26, 2022. https://assignbuster.com/a-commentary-on-theory-of-mind/.


Bibliography


AssignBuster. "A commentary on theory of mind." July 26, 2022. https://assignbuster.com/a-commentary-on-theory-of-mind/.

Work Cited

"A commentary on theory of mind." AssignBuster, 26 July 2022, assignbuster.com/a-commentary-on-theory-of-mind/.

Get in Touch

Please, let us know if you have any ideas on improving A commentary on theory of mind, or our service. We will be happy to hear what you think: [email protected]