2,158
25
Essay, 41 pages (10000 words)

Why is cognitive enhancement deemed unacceptable? the role of fairness, deservingness, and hollow achievements

Introduction

Pharmacological Cognitive Enhancement and Its Perceived Unacceptability

There are a number of means to enhance cognitive capacities beyond what is usually seen as compensation for an impairment. Nutrition and physical exercise improve cognitive functioning in healthy people across different domains (e. g., Dresler et al., 2013 ), whilst commonplace stimulants such as caffeine temporarily boost functions like alertness and concentration (e. g., Einöther and Giesbrecht, 2013 ). Use of these techniques is uncontroversial. Far more controversial is so-called “ brain doping,” that is the use of “ pharmacological interventions that are intended to improve certain mental functions and that go beyond currently accepted medical indications” ( Schermer et al., 2009 , p. 77).

Such pharmacological cognitive enhancement (PCE) may be achieved through the use of psychostimulants like methylphenidate (e. g., Ritalin ®) and wakefulness-promoting drugs like modafinil (e. g., Provigil ®). Research has demonstrated that these substances can have performance-enhancing effects in healthy individuals, for example by improving memory or attention (for reviews, see Repantis et al., 2010 ; Battleday and Brem, 2015 ; Ilieva et al., 2015 ). However, current PCE cannot enhance performance to more than modest degrees at best, depending on individual baseline performance ( Husain and Mehta, 2011 ; Caviola and Faber, 2015 ). Some societies have witnessed a rise in the use of PCE ( Care Quality Commission, 2013 ). Prevalence studies and informal polls suggest that at least some members of different groups use pharmacological substances with the goal to enhance their performance, for instance researchers ( Maher, 2008 ), surgeons ( Franke et al., 2013 ), and, across a range of countries, students (e. g., Singh et al., 2014 ; Maier et al., 2015 ; Schelle et al., 2015 ).

Pharmacological cognitive enhancement not only receives significant media attention, but is also intensively researched in a range of academic disciplines. These disciplines share the aim of understanding PCE (and mind-altering technologies in general) better, and helping society to deal with the challenges posed by increasing PCE use (cf. Greely et al., 2008 ; Smith and Farah, 2011 ; Sahakian et al., 2015 ). PCE is a truly interdisciplinary research topic, on which different disciplines can – and probably ought to – collaborate (cf. Hildt and Franke, 2013 ; Maslen et al., 2015 ). Neuroscience and the medical sciences investigate the pharmacological effects and potential side-effects of such substances (e. g., Turner et al., 2003 ). The behavioral and social sciences deal with questions such as what drives individuals to take PCE (e. g., Wolff and Brand, 2013 ), how members of the general public perceive PCE (e. g., Sattler et al., 2013 ), and which social consequences these perceptions might entail for users (e. g., Faulmüller et al., 2013 ). Meanwhile researchers in philosophy and law examine the ethical and legal problems PCE use entails, weigh these against possible benefits, and in some cases derive recommandations for public policy (e. g., Maslen et al., 2014a ) and legal regulation (e. g., Goold and Maslen, 2014 ). In doing so, they rely on empirical research, as both findings on the pharmacological effects of PCE (e. g., Maslen et al., 2014b ), as well as the public perception of PCE (e. g., Forlini et al., 2013 ) are crucial inputs into ethical, legal and policy debates regarding PCE.

Empirical studies on how members of the general public perceive PCE have already uncovered a variety of concerns people have about PCE, for example regarding medical safety (e. g., Scheske and Schnall, 2012 ) and societal inequality (e. g., Fitz et al., 2013 ; for a review, see Schelle et al., 2014 ). The – although often implicit – goal of many of these studies is to better understand one consistent finding, namely that PCE is deemed morally unacceptable (cf. Schelle et al., 2014 ). The judgment that “ PCE is morally unacceptable” – henceforth abbreviated as “ Unacceptability ” – is also found in media reports and in much of the normative debate. This article addresses the question: why do lay people endorse Unacceptability ? That is, why do they judge PCE to be morally unacceptable?

The Present Research: Combining Philosophical Rationales and Psychological Explanations

The primary innovation of our contribution is to employ an interdisciplinary perspective that combines normative philosophical and empirical psychological analyses. We propose that this combination provides a fruitful way to deepen understanding of why people generally judge PCE to be morally unacceptable. Philosophers who have explored moral responses to PCE have frequently, amongst other things, been interested in normative rationales, less in psychological explanations. That is, they have often not been asking why, as a matter of fact, people endorse a certain judgment, but why it might be rational to endorse it. Thus, no psychological conclusions can be straightforwardly drawn from philosophical work. However, we suggest that philosophical rationales can be useful in generating psychological hypotheses. As shown in the review by Schelle et al. (2014), lay attitudes on PCE tend to coincide with the attitudes of professional philosophers, suggesting that lay attitudes may have partly the same bases as professional philosophical attitudes. In other words, both philosophical rationalizations and lay attitudes might in part be expressions of a common rational thinking process, which philosophers make more explicit than lay people. (It is important to note, however, that intuitive lay judgments on PCE seem not always to be fully rational, Scheske and Schnall, 2012 ; cf. Caviola et al., 2014 ). Philosophical rationales for attitudes on PCE could thus be thought of as making explicit the psychological mechanisms that motivate acceptance of these attitudes in both philosophers and lay people, in so far as both groups form these attitudes rationally. Hence, we explore how philosophical rationales may aid psychology in identifying credible explanations for lay endorsement of Unacceptability .

We test the role of three judgments in explaining Unacceptability:(1) “ PCE produces unfair outcomes,” henceforth “ Unfairness ,” (2) “ achievements realized with the aid of PCE are “ hollow achievements” in the sense that they lack (some of their usual) value,” henceforth “ Hollowness ,” and (3) “ users of PCE do not deserve their achievements or the material and non-material reward associated with them,” henceforth “ Undeservingness .” Based on philosophical literature we generate two explanatory psychological models which are based on Unfairness , Hollowness , and Undeservingness , and test these against empirical data.

Philosophers have, implicitly or explicitly, endorsed or at least considered not only Unacceptability , but also Unfairness , Hollowness , and Undeservingness . More importantly, recent applied philosophical work on the ethics of cognitive enhancement has begun to explore the relationships between these views, and related work in theoretical philosophy could be deployed to further develop this understanding. Empirical work, in contrast, has consistently shown that lay people are concerned about unfairness induced by PCE use (cf. Schelle et al., 2014 ), but has not tested whether achievements realized with the help of PCE are seen as hollow or as undeserved or investigated the relationships between these views. Hence, it remains unclear precisely which, if any, of the judgments Unfairness , Hollowness , and Undeservingness contribute to lay endorsement of Unacceptability . For instance, is the perceived unacceptability of PCE explained by the judgment that it produces unfair outcomes, the judgment that users of cognitive enhancements do not deserve the reward they received, by both, or by neither? In addition, though it is possible that some or all of these judgments jointly explain support for Unacceptability , it is not clear (I) what relative contribution each judgment makes to this explanation; and (II) how, if at all, they interact. In this paper, we complement existing empirical research on the question of why lay people endorse Unacceptability by comparing three different factors ( Unfairness , Hollowness , and Undeservingness ) with regard to their relative strength in explaining the overall judgment of Unacceptability . We build on existing work by examining two judgments ( Hollowness and Undeservingness ) that have not previously been empirically investigated and by examining how the three judgments we consider interact with each other.

In sum, in this paper we combine philosophical rationales and psychological explanations to investigate why PCE is judged as morally unacceptable. We first outline two possible rationales for Unacceptability , drawing on both applied and theoretical philosophical work. We then offer two psychological models grounded on these rationales—the Unfairness-Undeservingness Model and the Hollowness-Undeservingness Model—and spell out our research questions regarding these models. Next, we describe our methods for testing these two models against empirical psychological data using a regression-based approach, before setting out the results of this testing. Finally, we discuss the implications of our findings for the psychology and philosophy of PCE.

Philosophical Rationales

The lay judgment we ultimately wish to explain— Unacceptability —holds that PCE is morally unacceptable. This judgment has been endorsed by a number of philosophers, who have considered a wide range of rationales for it. Broadly speaking, these can be divided into three categories: rationales that focus on the motives for which PCE is pursued (e. g., Little, 1998 ; Sandel, 2007 ), rationales that focus on the means by which it is pursued (e. g., The President’s Council on Bioethics (U. S.), 2003 ; Sandel, 2007 ), and rationales that focus on the consequences of pursuing it (e. g., Fukuyama, 2002 ; Elliott, 2003 ). In this section, our aim is not to offer a comprehensive review of all these rationales—this would be too ambitious a task (for a review, see Douglas, 2013 ). Rather, we limit ourselves to outlining rationales that meet two conditions. First, they appeal to one or more of the judgments Undeservingness , Hollowness , and Unfairness outlined above. Second, they are consequence-based, rather than motive- or means- based rationales. Our reason for limiting our discussion to consequence-based rationales is that adherents of a wide range of moral theories can accept such rationales. Almost all moral theories allow that an act or practice can be morally unacceptable because it has, or can be expected to have, bad consequences. By contrast, it is controversial whether an act can be morally unacceptable purely because of the means that it involves or the motives that produced it. 1

Two prominently discussed rationales meet our two conditions, namely what we call the “ objection from fairness” and the “ objection from hollow achievements.” In what follows, we set out our interpretations of these rationales.

The Objection from Fairness

A number of authors have endorsed, or at least considered, the view that PCE (or enhancement more generally) may be morally unacceptable because it is unfair or, perhaps equivalently, constitutes a form of “ cheating” (e. g., Fukuyama, 2002 ; The President’s Council on Bioethics (U. S.), 2003 ; Rose, 2006 ; Schermer, 2008 ). We call this the “ objection from fairness.” One variant of this objection holds that PCE is procedurally unfair: that it involves unfair means. This is a means- rather than consequence-based rationale for Unacceptability , and as such we do not discuss it further. A second variant of the objection holds that PCE is substantively unfair: that it produces unfair outcomes, as Unfairness holds. This variant of the objection is consequence-based, and will be our focus.

Two questions should be asked regarding this variant of the objection from fairness. First, why think that Unfairness supports Unacceptability ? Second, why accept Unfairness in the first place?

The answer to the first question is straightforward, though not normally made explicit in the literature on PCE: unfairness is bad, and as noted above, proponents of a range of moral theories can agree that, other things being equal, it is morally unacceptable to produce bad consequences. Why, precisely, unfairness is bad is controversial. Some hold that it is bad in itself (e. g., Broome, 1991 ). Others, would deny this and hold that fairness is only bad if and because it tends to produce further bad consequences, such as reduced individual wellbeing (e. g., Bentham, 1789 ; Sidgwick, 1893 ). However, despite this disagreement about why unfairness is bad, many agree that it is bad, or at least typically so.

The second question—why should we accept Unfairness —has caused greater controversy in the ethical debate regarding PCE. On the one hand, it seems “ obvious” ( The President’s Council on Bioethics (U. S.), 2003 , p. 280) or at least “ intuitive” ( Schermer, 2008 , p. 88) that some instances of enhancement, including PCE, produce unfairness. On the other hand, doubts can be raised about whether all enhancements, or all PCEs, do so (e. g., Savulescu, 2006 ; Douglas, 2007 ; Sandel, 2007 ; Schermer, 2008 ; Buchanan, 2011a , b ; Santoni de Sio et al., in press ). Hence, the scope of application of Unfairness is contested. There is also disagreement about how to rationalize Unfairness , that is about why enhancement produces unfairness when it does. One rationale holds that enhancement involves violating social rules or conventions, and it is unfair if individuals acquire reward through rule-violations (cf. Schermer, 2008 ). As has been noted, however, those who raise fairness-based concerns regarding enhancement frequently take these concerns to apply regardless whether the enhancement in question violates a rule ( Schermer, 2008 ; Savulescu, 2009 ). For instance, in the context of debate over enhancement in sport, concerns about production of unfairness have often been presented as a justification for maintaining prohibitions on enhancement rather than merely a consequence of such prohibitions (e. g., Lenk, 2007 ; Corlett et al., 2013 ). Similarly, philosophers concerned about fairness in relation to PCE have not generally restricted their concerns to rule-violating PCE ( Fukuyama, 2002 ; The President’s Council on Bioethics (U. S.), 2003 ). Hence, it seems appropriate to seek a more general rationale for Unfairness —one that will apply even in cases where PCE does not involve rule-violation. We suggest that Undeservingness might be able to furnish such a rationale (cf. also Schermer, 2008 ).

As defined above, Undeservingness is the judgment that PCE-users do not deserve their achievements or the material (e. g., money) and non-material (e. g., praise) reward associated with them. A number of authors in the debate on the ethics of enhancement have explicitly considered this view (e. g., Mehlman, 2004 ; Schermer, 2008 ; Forsberg, 2013 ), and it has been suggested ( Douglas, 2014 ) that a similar view may be implicit in the work of others ( Harris, 2012 ; Sparrow, 2014 ). Moreover, opponents of PCE frequently advance claims that can be understood to support Undeservingness. For instance, although disputed elsewhere ( Douglas, 2014 ), it is often said that enhancement makes achievements “ too easy” or is a way of avoiding effort ( Cole-Turner, 2000 ; Kass, 2003 ). If true, this might support Undeservingness , since exerting effort to overcome difficulties is often thought to confer deservingness ( Sadurski, 1985 ; Milne, 1986 ; Sorensen, 2010 ).

The relationship between Undeservingness and Unfairness has not been explored in detail in the applied philosophical literature on PCE (although cf. Mehlman, 2004 ; Schermer, 2008 ); however, it is plausible that the two judgments are normatively connected. One possibility is that Unfairness rationalizes Undeservingness —that is, because users of PCE are the beneficiaries of unfairness, they do not deserve their reward. Intuitively, people do not deserve unfairly acquired benefits. For instance, when an athlete breaks the rules of a sport and, as a result, wins a competition, we would conclude that she has won unfairly, and this may seem to support the view that she does not deserve the reward that come with the victory. This sort of case might seem to suggest that Unfairness is normatively more fundamental than Undeservingness .

However, theoretical work on the nature of fairness suggests that Undeservingness may be the more fundamental judgment: Undeservingness may be able to support Unfairness . 2 Some prominent theoretical accounts of fairness can be interpreted as holding that fairness, or at least one component of fairness, requires that (material or non-material) reward are distributed across individuals in proportion to the relative degree to which those individuals deserve those reward ( Broome, 1990 ; Feldman, 1995a ; Kagan, 2012 ). In support of this conception of the relationship between fairness and deservingness, consider the following case: Two charity workers undertake humanitarian projects in a poverty-stricken area without any expectation of reward. Their projects are very different in difficulty and scope. One spends several years single-handedly building a hospital that will save thousands of lives over the coming decades. The other spends one afternoon writing letters to local politicians, with the effect that those politicians divert an additional $500 to the provision of affordable pain relief medications. This can be expected to slightly increase the quality of life of each of 100 migraine sufferers for around a week. Intuitively, the first charity worker is more deserving than the second, all else equal, but it would be difficult to rationalize this judgment regarding deservingness by invoking the concept of fairness. On the other hand, the judgment regarding deservingness does seem potentially capable of rationalizing a judgment regarding fairness. Suppose both charity works receive similar levels of praise for their efforts. Intuitively, this is unfair. The first charity working deserves more praise, and it seems unfair if he does not get it.

A similar line of reasoning suggests that Unfairness may be able to rationalize Undeservingness . Imagine a case in which two scientists, A and B , make similar and highly significant scientific discoveries. Suppose, however, that A made her discovery assisted by PCE which allowed her to work longer hours and more productively, whereas B made the discovery without any such pharmacological assistance. Although we do not ourselves endorse this view, according to Undeservingness, A does not deserve her achievement or the praise, academic success, and other reward that accompany it, perhaps because her enhancement allows her to avoid effort, or made her achievement “ too easy.” On the other hand, it is plausible to assume that B does deserve her achievement and associated reward, at least to some extent. However, despite this difference in deservingness, it is likely that these two scientists will receive a similar size of reward for these achievements, at least if A ’s PCE-use is secret (cf. Faulmüller et al., 2013 ). Thus, rewards are not distributed in proportion to deservingness, and this, on the present conception of fairness, is unfair. Hence, if (1) Undeservingness holds true, and 2) PCE users are rewarded to a similar degree as non-users who achieve similar things, then use of PCE may disrupt fairness.

The Objection from Hollow Achievements

A second candidate rationale for Unacceptability invokes Hollowness —the claim that achievements realized with the aid of PCE are “ hollow achievements” in the sense that they lack (some of their normal) value. This claim, or variants thereof, have been endorsed by a number of authors in the ethical debate on PCE, and enhancement more generally. Juengst (2000) raised the question whether achievements realized via enhancement might be “ hollow accomplishments” (p. 39), and The President’s Council on Bioethics (U. S.) (2003) claimed that enhancements would undermine the “ dignity” (p. 140) of human performance and perhaps render that performance “ false” (p. 131), thereby highlighting two specific values (dignity and truth) that enhancements might threaten. In what follows, we focus on the question whether PCE might deprive human achievements of some degree of value without taking a stance on what particular kind of value that might be. Following Juengst’s terminology, we call this the “ objection from hollowness.”

As with the objection from fairness, two questions should be asked regarding the objection from hollowness. First, why think that Hollowness supports Unacceptability ? Second, why accept Hollowness ?

On the first question, why Hollowness supports Unacceptability , little has been said. However, it is possible to construct a straightforward argument from Hollowness to Unacceptability . According to Hollowness , achievements realized with the aid of PCE lack (some of their normal) value, and this means that pursuit of enhancement has at least one bad consequence: it diminishes at least some forms of value that our achievements might otherwise have had.

More has been said on the second question: why accept Hollowness ? That is, why judge achievements gained with the help of PCE to be hollow achievements? On one view, PCE use can devalue achievements because it corrupts the very purpose of the activity being pursued (e. g., Santoni de Sio et al., in press ). In this regard, using an enhancement might – to take an often-cited example – be like completing a marathon with the aid of roller skates ( Whitehouse et al., 1997 ). Some activities (including marathon running) fulfill their purpose only where pursued in a certain kind of way, and in some cases enhancement is incompatible with the required manner of execution. This may be because the activities in question only have value when they manifest a certain kind of human contribution, and the use of enhancement somehow negates the need for any such contribution ( Savulescu, 2015 ). However, as many have noted, not all activities are such that their purpose is undermined when they are pursued with the aid of enhancements (e. g,. Douglas, 2007 ; Bostrom and Roache, 2008 ; Roache, 2008 ; Schermer, 2008 ; Goodman, 2010 ; Santoni de Sio et al., in press ). Consider landing an airplane or performing a surgical operation. The purpose of these activities is to realize a certain outcome, and the realization of that outcome need not be threatened, and may even be aided, by the use of enhancements (cf. Santoni de Sio et al., 2014 ). Moreover, activities that would be rendered hollow by very extensive enhancements may not be rendered hollow by more modest ones. For instance, climbing Mount Everest with the aid of a jetpack might render it a hollow achievement, but it is far less clear that climbing with the aid of compressed oxygen, or regular morning coffees, does so. Hence, we think that the present argument cannot support the claim that, generally, achievements realized via PCE are hollow, as some have suggested (e. g., The President’s Council on Bioethics (U. S.), 2003 ). As with Unfairness , then, it is desirable to seek a more general rationale for Hollowness. And as with Unfairness , we suggest that it may be possible to provide such a rationale by using Undeservingness.

It is often thought that things that are normally valuable can lack this value when they are not deserved. For instance, pleasure is normally valuable—it normally makes the world a better place when a person experiences pleasure—but some argue that it lacks its normal value when it is not deserved (e. g., Brentano, 1969 ; Feldman, 1995b ). Hence, on this view, pleasure is, other things being equal, less valuable when it is enjoyed by a mass-murderer than when it is enjoyed by an innocent person. Similar thoughts may apply to valuable achievements. It may be that, when achievements are underserved, they lack value. If so, and if PCE undermines deservingness, then achievements realized with the aid of PCE lack value—that is, Hollowness holds true. 3

The Unfairness-Undeservingness Model and the Hollowness-Undeservingness Model

Based on philosophical literature on PCE and on relevant work in moral theory, we have outlined two possible philosophical rationales for Unacceptability , that is the claim that PCE is morally unacceptable. According to the first rationale, the objection from fairness, Unacceptability can be rationalized by appeal to Unfairness and Undeservingness . According to the second rationale, the objection from hollowness, Unacceptability can be rationalized by appeal to Hollowness and Undeservingness.

We do not claim that these rationales constitute the only plausible ways of understanding the normative relationships between these judgments. For one thing, we have limited ourselves to rationales that can be understood as appealing to bad consequences of enhancement, yet we do not rule out the possibility that there are plausible motive- or means-based rationales for Unacceptability . For another, there may be consequence-based rationales for Unacceptability that we have not considered. We also do not claim that these rationales are in the end successful; indeed, one of us has previously argued against a view similar to Undeservingness ( Douglas, 2014 ). However, we do claim the two rationales we have outlined are among the prima facie plausible rationales for Unacceptability.

Based on the idea that philosophical justifications can form the basis for psychological models, we derive two such models from our theoretical analyses above.

(1)The Unfairness-Undeservingness Model : People judge PCE to be unacceptable because they take it to produce unfairness and undermine the degree to which PCE-users deserve their achievement and associated reward. In other words, lay judgments of Unacceptability can be jointly explained by Unfairness and Undeservingness .

(2)The Hollowness-Undeservingness Model : People judge PCE to be unacceptable because they find achievements while using PCE hollow and undeserved. In other words, lay judgments of Unacceptability can be jointly explained by Hollowness and Undeservingness .

Note that in our philosophical analysis we discuss different possibilities for causal relationships between Unfairness and Undeservingness and between Hollowness and Undeservingness , respectively. For the sake of starting out with parsimonious models for empirical testing, we do not specify causal relationships beyond causes for Unacceptability in the psychological part. However, we return to the issue of a causal order of the explanatory variables in the discussion of our empirical results.

Research Questions

The purpose of this paper is to combine normative philosophical and empirical psychological analyses to gain a deeper understanding of why people generally judge PCE to be morally unacceptable. We have derived two philosophically informed models for possible psychological explanations. Based on our theoretical analyses, we formulate the following two research questions.

(I) How well can the judgments Undeservingness , Unfairness , and Hollowness explain Unacceptability ?

(II) How do these judgments interact, that is, more specifically: which of the two models, the Unfairness-Undeservingness Model or the Hollowness-Undeservingness Model, is better supported by empirical data?

In what follows, we report a test of these philosophy-grounded research questions against empirical data.

Psychological Explanations

Methods

We tested our research questions by re-analyzing parts of a larger data set we had collected and reported on previously (for details, see Faber et al., 2015a ). For 94 participants, this data set contains information on the PCE-related judgments of interest, that is answers on Undeservingness , Unfairness , Hollowness , and Unacceptability . (The other participants in the complete data set did not answer questions in relation to cognitive enhancement but on motivation enhancement, so their judgments are not relevant for the present study. Please see Faber et al. (2015a) for further details on this data set.) Hence, our present sample contained 94 U. S. American participants (48% female, mean age 36. 9 years 4 ), who indicated that they had not previously used PCE. All respondents completed the study online. They gave informed consent to participate and were compensated financially for their participation. This study had been reviewed and approved by the University of Oxford’s Medical Sciences Interdivisional Research Ethics Committee.

After answering demographic questions, each participant read a hypothetical scenario about a male student who uses PCE. The part of the scenario describing this use read as follows: “ While preparing for his exams, Alex takes medical substances to help him with his work. These pills normally are available on prescription only to treat certain diseases, but Alex knows that they improve brain performance in healthy people. They can make people think faster and more clearly. By taking these “ smart pills,” he hopes to do better in his exams.” After participants had read the scenario, they answered several questions on 7-point Likert-scales (1 = “ completely disagree”; 7 = “ completely agree”). There was one item each for Undeservingness (“ If Alex does well in his exams, he deserves praise,” reversely coded) and for Hollowness (“ If Alex does well in his exams, it will be a hollow achievement”). To capture the frequent use of the more familiar concept of “ cheating” to express concerns about unfairness, we included two items for Unfairness , one referring explicitly to the concept of unfairness (“ It will be unfair if Alex does better in his exams than his classmates who don’t take the “ smart pills”) and one to “ cheating” (“ Taking “ smart pills” is cheating”). We used the mean of both items, which were highly correlated [ r (92) = 0. 842, p < 0. 001], in subsequent analyses. (The pattern of results reported below remains unchanged when only the explicit unfairness item or the “ cheating” item is included.) Finally, we assessed participants’ global judgment about Unacceptability (“ Taking medical substances that improve smartness is acceptable”; reversely coded). (For further questions asked that are not relevant for this re-analysis and, hence, not reported below, see Faber et al., 2015a .)

Results

To answer our research questions (I) how well the factors Undeservingness , Unfairness , and Hollowness can explain Unacceptability , and (II) which of the two proposed models, the Unfairness-Undeservingness Model and the Hollowness-Undeservingness Model, is better supported by our data, we used a regression-based approach. 5

Descriptive Statistics

To begin with, to get a sense of the general view of Unacceptability in our sample, we performed a descriptive analysis. This analysis showed that the mean level of agreement that PCE is unacceptable was 4. 70 ( SD = 1. 72); the median agreement was scale point 5 (“ somewhat agree”). 58. 6% of participants agreed (between strongly and somewhat) to Unacceptability , while 30. 9% disagreed (between strongly and somewhat). The remaining 10. 6% were undecided. Hence, in line with previous findings on non-users, participants in our sample on average exhibited support for Unacceptability , although there was a considerable variance in this view.

Similarly, we looked at the descriptive statistics for Unfairness , Hollowness , and Undeservingness . The mean level of agreement for Unfairness was 4. 70 ( SD = 1. 76), and the median 5. The percentage of participants agreeing to Unfairness was 59. 6%, and 27. 7% disagreed. For Hollowness , the mean was 4. 15 ( SD = 1. 79), and the median was 4. 45. 7% of participants agreed to Hollowness , and 41. 5% disagreed. For Undeservingness , the mean was 3. 76 ( SD = 1. 61), the median 3. 33. 1% agreed with Undeservingness , 51. 1% disagreed. Hence, while the participants in our sample judged PCE as unfair on average, they were divided on the view whether its use makes achievements hollow, and overall did not agree with the claim that achievements gained with PCE are generally undeserved.

The Unfairness-Undeservingness Model

We tested the degree to which variations in agreement to Unfairness and Undeservingness could explain variations in agreement to Unacceptability , thereby evaluating the ability of the Unfairness-Undeservingness Model to explain the perceived unacceptability of PCE.

We conducted a linear regression analysis with Unacceptability as dependent variable and Unfairness and Undeservingness as predictors. Our two predictors explained a significant amount of the variance in the dependent variable [ F (2, 91) = 27. 80, p < 0. 001, R 2 = 0. 379, R 2 adjusted = 0. 366]. However, in this regression only Unfairness was a significant predictor of Unacceptability [β = 0. 48, t (91) = 3. 72, p < 0. 001], while Undeservingness had no significant explanatory power beyond Unacceptability [β = 0. 16, t (91) = 1. 27, p = 0. 208]. ( Unfairness and Undeservingness were significantly correlated [ r (92) = 0. 769, p < 0. 001], but multi-collinearity statistics showed no reason for concern in our data for this regression analysis ( Unfairness : Tolerance = 0. 409, VIF = 2. 446; Undeservingness : Tolerance = 0. 409, VIF = 2. 446).

In sum, while the Unfairness-Undeservingness Model can account for about 38% of the variance in Unacceptability judgments, its explanatory power is mainly driven by Unfairness .

The Hollowness-Undeservingness Model

Analogously to the calculations for the Unfairness-Undeservingness Model, we tested the plausibility of the Hollowness-Undeservingness Model in explaining Unacceptability .

A linear regression analysis with Unacceptability as dependent variable and Hollowness and Undeservingness as predictors showed that the two predictors significantly explained the dependent variable [ F (2, 91) = 22. 72, p < 0. 001, R 2 = 0. 333, R 2 adjusted = 0. 318]. In this regression, Hollowness was a significant predictor of Unacceptability [β = 0. 35, t (91) = 2. 57, p = 0. 012], and Undeservingness had marginally significant explanatory power [β = 0. 26, t (91) = 1. 89, p = 0. 062]. ( Hollowness and Undeservingness were significantly correlated [ r (92) = 0. 781, p < 0. 001], but multi-collinearity statistics showed no reason for concern regarding the reliability of our data ( Hollowness : Tolerance = 0. 390, VIF = 2. 564 ; Undeservingness : Tolerance = 0. 390, VIF = 2. 564).

In sum, when regarded on its own (i. e., not in comparison to the Unfairness-Undeservingness Model), the Hollowness-Undeservingness Model explains about 33% of Unacceptability , with the influence of Undeservingness being only marginally significant.

Comparing the Unfairness-Undeservingness Model and the Hollowness-Undeservingness Model

In a further step, we compared the Hollowness-Undeservingness Model to the Unfairness-Undeservingness Model, looking at whether the former has any power in explaining Unacceptability beyond the Unfairness-Undeservingness Model.

We used all three factors Unfairness, Hollowness , and Undeservingness , as predictors in a linear regression with Unacceptability as dependent variable. We found that Hollowness as an additional predictor only added 1. 2% to the explanatory power of the Unfairness-Undeservingness Model, which is a non-significant change [ F (1, 90) = 1. 73, p = 0. 193, R 2 = 0. 391, R 2 adjusted = 0. 371]. Correspondingly, with all three predictors in the regression analysis, only Unfairness had a significant influence on Unacceptability [β = 0. 41, t (90) = 2. 93, p = 0. 004], while both Undeservingness [β = 0. 07, t (90) = 0. 50, p = 0. 662] and Hollowness [β = 0. 19, t (91) = 1. 31, p = 0. 193] had none. Again, Hollowness was significantly correlated with both Undeservingness [ r (92) = 0. 781, p < 0. 001] and Unfairness [ r (92) = 0. 757, p < 0. 001], but collinearity statistics seemed unproblematic ( Unfairness : Tolerance = 0. 346, VIF = 2. 888; Hollowness : Tolerance = 0. 330, VIF = 3. 027 ; Undeservingness : Tolerance = 0. 316, VIF = 3. 164).

This model comparison reveals the importance of Unfairness in explaining Unacceptability . Both Hollowness [β = 0. 55, t (92) = 6. 38, p = 0. 001] and Undeservingness [β = 0. 53, t (92) = 6. 05, p < 0. 001] are significantly associated with Unacceptability when considered on their own, that is, as sole predictors. As soon as Unfairness is taken into account, however, they do not show any additional power in explaining Unacceptability. Put differently, while all three factors Unfairness , Hollowness , and Undeservingness jointly can explain about 39% of Unacceptability , Unfairness alone already explains about 36% [ F (1, 92) = 53. 64, p < 0. 001, R 2 = 0. 361, R 2 adjusted = 0. 361]. This 2. 3% improvement in explanation Hollowness and Undeservingness can bring is statistically insignificant ( p = 0. 193, as reported above).

In sum, this analysis showed that the Unfairness-Undeservingness Model is superior to the Hollowness-Undeservingness Model in explaining Unacceptability , and that this superiority is driven by Unfairness . Amongst the three predictors Unfairness , Hollowness , and Undeservingness , Unfairness is the only one making a contribution in explaining Unacceptability beyond the two others.

Discussion

In this paper, we aimed to gain a deeper understanding of why people generally endorse Unacceptability , that is judge PCE as morally unacceptable. For that, we combined normative philosophical and empirical psychological analyses.

The Central Role of Unfairness in Explaining the Unacceptability of PCE

Based on philosophical literature, we argued that three judgments could be deployed to normatively rationalize Unacceptability , namely Unfairness (the idea that PCE produces unfair outcomes), Hollowness (the idea that achievements gained with PCE are hollow achievements), and Undeservingness (the idea that users of PCE are less deserving of reward). We developed philosophical rationales that combined these three judgments in different ways and, based on these rationales, proposed two psychological models that could potentially explain why lay people 4 endorse Unacceptability . The Unfairness-Undeservingness Model holds that judgments of Unacceptability can be jointly explained by Unfairness and Undeservingness , and the Hollowness-Undeservingness Model holds that judgments of Unacceptability can be jointly explained by Hollowness and Undeservingness . We formulated two research questions: (I) How well can Undeservingness , Unfairness , and Hollowness can explain Unacceptability ? And (II) is the Unfairness-Undeservingness Model or the Hollowness-Undeservingness Model better supported by empirical data?

We then tested these two research questions in a sample of lay people who indicated that they had not previously used PCE, using a regression-based approach. Descriptively, while participants tended to agree with the overall statements that PCE is unacceptable ( Unacceptability ) and with the claim that it is unfair ( Unfairness ), they were divided on the question whether it leads to achievements being hollow ( Hollowness ), and, on average, they tended to disagree with the idea that achievements gained with PCE are undeserved ( Undeservingness ).

With regards to our first research question, we found that Unfairness was clearly the strongest predictor of Unacceptability , explaining about 36% of the variance in Unacceptability judgments. While the two remaining judgments, Hollowness and Undeservingness , were also able to significantly predict Unacceptability when considered as sole predictors, they had no significant influence over and above Unfairness . All three predictors combined explained about 39% of variance. In other words, although people who judge PCE to be unacceptable also judge accomplishments gained with help of PCE to be undeserved and these achievements to be hollow, the two latter factors seem not to be necessary to explain why people endorse Unacceptability. All they can contribute to the explanation is just as well explained by Unfairness alone. Concerns about unfairness, on the other hand, seem to be central in understanding why PCE is judged as unacceptable.

With regards to our second research question, we consequently found that the Unfairness-Undeservingness Model was superior to the Hollowness-Undeservingness Model in explaining Unacceptability . While, again, the Hollowness-Undeservingness Model appeared to well explain Unacceptability when regarded on its own, a direct comparison to the Unfairness-Undeservingness Model showed that it did not make any contribution to understanding why PCE is judged as unacceptable beyond what we gain from the Unfairness-Undeservingness Model. Hence, if we are to accept one of these models, we should accept the Unfairness-Undeservingness Model.

Importantly, however, in the Undeservingness-Unfairness Model, Unfairness was the only predictor to make a significant contribution in explaining Unacceptability , while Undeservingness was not. What implications does this fact have for the Unfairness-Undeservingness Model?

An “ Unfairness Model” or Unfairness as Mediating Variable?

When we proposed the Unfairness-Undeservingness Model, we hypothesized that “ people find PCE unacceptable because they take it to produce unfairness and undermine the degree to which the PCE-user deserves her achievement and associated reward. In other words, lay judgments of Unacceptability can be jointly explained by Unfairness and Undeservingness .” We found, however, that when we have knowledge about Unfairness , we do not need Undeservingness to explain Unacceptability . There seem to be two plausible possibilities of how this can be interpreted. It could be taken to support either a single-factor “ Unfairness Model,” or the view that Unfairness acts as the mediating variable within the Unfairness-Undeservingness Model.

The straight-forward conclusion from our findings would be to propose a model we could call the “ Unfairness Model.” An ideal model is one that offers a good trade-off between parsimoniousness and explanatory power. As Unfairness alone explains Unacceptability just as well as the Unfairness-Undeservingness Model, it seems appropriate to just reject Undeservingness and to propose a model that is based solely on Unfairness . This Unfairness Model could, of course, not fully explain why people judge PCE as morally unacceptable, but it could explain around 36% of variance in Unacceptability judgments, which is a considerable amount. Proposing such an Unfairness Model would imply that Undeservingness (and also Hollowness ) are purely epiphenomenal. That is, people find PCE morally unacceptable because they find it unfair. And, when they find it unfair, then they judge achievements realized with it to also be undeserved (and hollow). This would be consistent with the view that Unfairness may rationalize Undeservingness , rather than the reverse (cf. section The Objection from Fairness).

There is, however, a second possibility that is consistent with our data. The Unfairness-Undeservingness Model could still be a plausible model, with the relationship between Undeservingness and Unacceptability being mediated by Unfairness. As described above, our original version of the Unfairness-Undeservingness Model proposed that “ judgments of Unacceptability can be jointly explained by Unfairness and Undeservingness .” While it seems that “ jointly” is not correct (as Undeservingness doesn’t add anything to this joint explanation), it might be that Undeservingness influences Unacceptability via Unfairness . This would imply that people find PCE unacceptable because they find it unfair, and they find it unfair because they find achievements realized with it undeserved. Such a causal chain would be in line both with our data and with philosophical considerations. While we find Undeservingness to be a significant predictor of Unacceptability , this relationship breaks down as soon as we add Unfairness as a second predictor. If, statistically, Unfairness were a full mediator of the relationship between Undeservingness and Unacceptability , we would expect such a result. Moreover, while no causal order between the variables Unfairness and Undeservingness has been assumed in our psychological model, it has been implicit in our philosophical rationales: in the section on “ the objection from fairness,” we suggested that Undeservingness may rationalize Unfairness which in turn may rationalize Unacceptability. Hence, our philosophical analysis suggests a causal chain leading from Undeservingness over Unfairness to Unacceptability .

Unfortunately, based on our analyses we cannot assess which of the above possibilities (a single-factor Unfairness Model or Unfairness as the mediating variable in the Unfairness-Undeservingness Model) is true. Path analyses could give a good indication in larger samples, and controlled experiments could provide strong conclusions. We hope that future research will shed further light on the relationship between Undeservingness and Unfairness .

Importantly, however, both possibilities have at their core the same conclusion, namely that Unfairness plays a central role in explaining Unacceptability , and that we would need to understand why people find PCE unfair if we want to understand why they find it morally unacceptable. Or, put differently, it might well be that a lot of support for the view that PCE is unacceptable would dissolve if PCE was seen as fair. And indeed, concerns about the unfairness of PCE loom large in both the normative debate (e. g., Fukuyama, 2002 ; The President’s Council on Bioethics (U. S.), 2003 ; Gazzaniga, 2006 ; Rose, 2006 ) and lay people’s concerns (e. g., Forlini and Racine, 2012 ; Scheske and Schnall, 2012 ; Bossaer et al., 2013 ; Dubljevic et al., 2014 ; Santoni de Sio et al., in press for a review, see Schelle et al., 2014 , p. 8–11). However, again, to date we cannot be certain what the causal relationship between Unfairness and Unacceptability is. So while PCE could be seen as unacceptable because it is seen as unfair, it might also be the other way around (PCE may be seen as unfair because seen as unacceptable), or bi-directional.

Understanding the Psychology of PCE

The approach followed in this paper had two core elements. First, we took an interdisciplinary stance by combining normative philosophical and empirical psychological analyses. Second, we tried to shed light on how different normative judgments on PCE are related to each other psychologically. We hope that our approach has not only helped to advance research on the specific question why PCE is generally found unacceptable, but also to illustrate how philosophical analyses can be helpful in understanding the psychology of PCE.

With regards to interdisciplinarity, we hope to have shown how hypotheses derived from philosophical reasoning can serve as guideline about which psychological relationships are fruitful for testing. It would also be interesting, we think, to explore the reverse strategy, that is to use psychological findings to generate philosophical “ hypotheses” than can be tested by normative or conceptual analyses. It might, for example, be worthwhile for philosophers to consider whether Undeservingness and Hollowness could be normatively epiphenomenal, in the sense that they are implications of Unfairness but play no role in the rationalization of Unacceptability by Unfairness.

With regards to our aim to test relations between different judgments on PCE, we think that this is not only worthwhile, but necessary both from an academic and a practical perspective. When we want to understand the psychology of cognitive enhancement, that is how human beings react to PCE and other mind-altering technologies, we need to gain more than a list of reactions these technologies evoke. Rather, we need to know which reactions are cause, and which are consequence; which are central and which are epiphenomenal.

Understanding the psychology of PCE, in turn, is necessary to estimate the non-pharmacological consequences of PCE use. Psychological reactions based on subjective judgments about PCE can be powerful. For instance, people tend to subjectively judge PCE as more effective than it actually is ( Ilieva et al., 2013 ) and some employ it to cope with elevated stress (e. g., Wiegel et al., 2015 ). However, consuming PCE seems to be detrimental to reducing stress, but on the contrary weakens the protective effect of internal personal resources against burnout ( Wolff et al., 2014 ). Moreover, it has been argued that the prevalent negative judgments of others regarding PCE can cause considerable psychological costs for users (for example reduced self-esteem; Faulmüller et al., 2013 ).

Increased understanding of psychological processes is also crucial for assessing the consequences PCE has beyond individual users. Current pharmacological research on the effectiveness of PCE substances measures how they influence participants’ individual performance. Based on such research, it has been argued that the use of PCE would also be beneficial on a societal level, for example, because enhancements will increase human productivity, resulting in general economic benefits through either greater availability of goods or lower prices ( Bostrom and Ord, 2006 ; Buchanan, 2008 , 2011a , b ). However, a psychological understanding of normative attitudes to enhancement could complicate this picture. Employing a psychological perspective, it has been illustrated that the effect of PCE on an individual’s performance can be increased, but also be reduced, completely eliminated or even reversed at a group level ( Faber et al., 2015b ): The effectiveness of PCE in improving group performance depends on the psychological processes within the group, which, in turn, is guided by the subjective judgments the group members make about PCE. If, for example, group members who do not use PCE form negative attitudes to PCE-users, this can lead to these two parties not interacting efficiently and not functioning well as a performance group. In such a case, even though a PCE substance is an enhancement of individual performance (for pharmacological reasons), it could even act as an impairment for a group (for psychological reasons). Therefore, subjective judgments about PCE can determine the performance benefits groups can – or cannot – draw from PCE.

Hence, if we want to know how PCE affects us as a society, we need to understand not only the pharmacology, but also the psychology associated with such technologies. We think that both employing an interdisciplinary perspective and investigating the relationships between judgments on PCE is fruitful to understand this psychology. At present, research on the public perception of PCE and its consequences is still in its infancy. We hope that in the near future we will have a more comprehensive and coherent picture of the psychology of PCE – both for our academic understanding of human enhancement and to assist policy making.

Author Contributions

NF and TD developed the models. NF analyzed the data. NF, JS, and TD wrote the paper.

Conflict of Interest Statement

The authors declare that the research was conducted in the absence of any commercial or financial relationships that could be construed as a potential conflict of interest.

Acknowledgments

The authors have been supported by the Oxford Martin School [Oxford Martin Programme on Resource Stewardship], the Uehiro Foundation on Ethics and Education, and the Wellcome Trust [100705/Z/12/Z and 086041/Z/08/Z].

Footnotes

  1. ^ Consequentialist moral theories hold that the moral status of an act is determined solely by its consequences (cf. Skorupski, 1995 ; Sinnott-Armstrong, 2001 ). On this view, the only reason that an act can be morally unacceptable (or “ impermissible” or, simply, “ wrong”) is that it has or can be expected to have bad consequences, or worse consequences than the alternatives. Deontological and virtue-ethical moral theories, such as those advanced by Immanuel Kant (e. g., 1786/2013 ) and Aristotle (e. g., trans, 2014) and their respective followers, hold that further considerations may be relevant. On most such theories, an act can be unacceptable even though it produces good (or the best possible) consequences. For instance, on a deontological theory, a good-maximizing act may be unacceptable because it violates someone’s rights or breaks the terms of a contract. On a virtue-ethical theory, it may be unacceptable because it is not what a virtuous agent would have done. However, deontological and virtue-ethical theories typically allow that the value of the consequences of an act remain relevant to the moral status of the act, and that an act can in some cases be morally unacceptable because it produces bad consequences which there is a duty not to produce, or which a fully virtuous agent would not produce (cf. Bennett, 1989 ; Hursthouse, 1991 ).
  2. ^ A third possibility is that Unfairness and Undeservingness are logically connected though neither is more fundamental than the other. For instance, it may be that to say that X enjoys an unfair advantage over Y is just to say that A does not deserve her advantage.
  3. ^ Again, however, other conceptions of the relationship between Deservingness and Hollowness are also plausible. For instance, it may be that when a person realizes an achievement without making the appropriate kind of human contribution, this independently renders both the achievement hollow and the achiever undeserving of reward.
  4. ^ Our participants were of mixed gender, age, as well as educational and socioeconomic backgrounds. They all lived in the USA, however, and in this sense our sample is quite restricted. We cannot be sure that our results can be generalized to people from other cultural backgrounds.
  5. ^ Using regression analyses seemed most appropriate to us given our specific research questions, but also in light of the ongoing debate on the statistical (in)appropriateness of dichotomizing continuous variables via median splits to use ANOVAs (e. g., Rucker et al., 2015 ).

References

Battleday, R. M., and Brem, A.-K. (2015). Modafinil for cognitive neuroenhancement in healthy non-sleep-deprived subjects: a systematic review. Eur. Neuropsychopharmacol. 25, 1865–1881. doi: 10. 1016/j. euroneuro. 2015. 07. 028

||

Bennett, J. (1989). Two departures from consequentialism. Ethics 100, 54–66. doi: 10. 1086/293144

|

Bentham, J. (1789). An Introduction to the Principles of Morals and Legislation. Oxford: Clarendon Press.

Bossaer, J. B., Gray, J. A., Miller, S. E., Enck, G., Gaddipati, V. C., and Enck, R. E. (2013). The use and misuse of prescription stimulants as “ cognitive enhancers” by students at one academic health sciences center. Acad. Med. 88, 967–971. doi: 10. 1097/Acm. 0b013e318294fc7b

||

Bostrom, N., and Ord, T. (2006). The reversal test: eliminating status quo bias in applied ethics. Ethics 116, 656–679. doi: 10. 1086/505233

||

Bostrom, N., and Roache, R. (2008). “ Ethical issues in human enhancement,” in New Waves in Applied Ethics , eds J. Ryberg, T. S. Petersen, and C. Wolf (Hampshire: Palgrave Macmillan), 120–152.

Brentano, F. (1969). “ Loving and hating”, in The Origin of Our Knowledge of Right and Wrong , ed. O. Krause and R. Chisolm, trans. R. Chisholm and E. Schneewind (London: Routledge & Kegan-Paul), 154–155.

Broome, J. (1990). Fairness. Proc. Aristotel. Soc. 91, 87–102. doi: 10. 1093/aristotelian/91. 1. 87

|

Broome, J. (1991). Weighing Goods. Oxford: Basil Blackwell.

Buchanan, A. (2008). Enhancement and the ethics of development. Kennedy Inst. Ethics J. 18, 1–34. doi: 10. 1353/ken. 0. 0003

|

Buchanan, A. (2011a). Beyond Humanity? The Ethics of Biomedical Enhancement. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

Buchanan, A. (2011b). Better than Human: The Promise and Perils of Enhancing Ourselves. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

Care Quality Commission (2013). The Safer Management of Controlled Drugs: Annual Report 2012. Available at: http://www.cqc.org.uk/sites/default/files/documents/cdar_2012.pdf [accessed August 26, 2015].

Caviola, L., and Faber, N. S. (2015). Pills or push-ups? Effectiveness and public perception of pharmacological and non-pharmacological cognitive enhancement. Front. Psychol. 6: 1852. doi: 10. 3389/fpsyg. 2015. 01852

||

Caviola, L., Mannino, A., Savulescu, J., and Faulmüller, N. (2014). Cognitive biases can affect moral intuitions about cognitive enhancement. Front. Syst. Neurosci. 8: 195. doi: 10. 3389/fnsys. 2014. 00195

||

Cole-Turner, R. (2000). “ Do means matter,” in Enhancing Human Traits: Ethical and Social Implications , ed. E. Parens (Washington, DC: Georgetown University Press), 151–161.

Corlett, J. A., Brown, V. Jr., and Kirkland, K. (2013). Coping with doping. J. Philos. Sport 40, 41–64. doi: 10. 1080/00948705. 2012. 725897

|

Douglas, T. (2007). Enhancement in sport, and enhancement outside sport. Stud. Ethics Law Technol. 1, 1–11. doi: 10. 2202/1941-6008. 1000

|

Douglas, T. (2013). “ Enhancement, biomedical,” in International Encyclopedia of Ethics , ed. H. LaFollette (Malden, MA: Wiley-Blackwell).

Douglas, T. (2014). Enhancing moral conformity and enhancing moral worth. Neuroethics 7, 75–91. doi: 10. 1007/s12152-013-9183-y

||

Dresler, M., Sandberg, A., Ohla, K., Bublitz, C., Trenado, C., Mroczko-Waksowicz, A., et al. (2013). Non-pharmacological cognitive enhancement. Neuropharmacology 64, 529–543. doi: 10. 1016/j. neuropharm. 2012. 07. 002

||

Dubljevic, V., Sattler, S., and Racine, E. (2014). Cognitive enhancement and academic misconduct: a study exploring their frequency and relationship. Ethics Behav. 24, 408–420. doi: 10. 1080/10508422. 2013. 869747

|

Einöther, S. J., and Giesbrecht, T. (2013). Caffeine as an attention enhancer: reviewing existing assumptions. Psychopharmacology (Berl.) 225, 251–274. doi: 10. 1007/s00213-012-2917-4

||

Elliott, C. (2003). Better than Well: American Medicine Meets the American Dream. New York, NY: Norton.

Faber, N. S., Douglas, T., Heise, F., and Hewstone, M. (2015a). Cognitive enhancement and motivation enhancement – an empirical comparison of intuitive judgments. Am. J. Bioethics Neurosci. 13, 18–20. doi: 10. 1080/21507740. 2014. 991847

|

Faber, N. S., Häusser, J. A., and Kerr, N. L. (2015b). Sleep deprivation impairs and caffeine enhances my performance, but not always our performance: how acting in a group can change the effects of impairments and enhancements. Pers. Soc. Psychol. Rev. doi: 10. 1177/1088868315609487 [Epub ahead of print].

||

Faulmüller, N., Maslen, H., and Santoni de Sio, F. (2013). The indirect psychological costs of cognitive enhancement. Am. J. Bioeth. 13, 45–47. doi: 10. 1080/15265161. 2013. 794880

||

Feldman, F. (1995a). Adjusting utility for justice: a consequentialist reply to the objection from Justice. Philos. Phenomen. Res. 55, 567–585. doi: 10. 2307/2108439

|

Feldman, F. (1995b). Justice, desert, and the repugnant conclusion. Utilitas 7, 189–206. doi: 10. 1017/S095382080000203X

|

Fitz, N. S., Nadler, R., Manogaran, P., Chong, E. W. J., and Reiner, P. B. (2013). Public attitudes toward cognitive enhancement. Neuroethics 7, 173–188. doi: 10. 1007/s12152-013-9190-z

|

Forlini, C., and Racine, E. (2012). Added stakeholders, added value(s) to the cognitive enhancement debate: are academic discourse and professional policies sidestepping values of stakeholders? AJOB Prim. Res. 3, 33–47. doi: 10. 1080/21507716. 2011. 645116

|

Forlini, C., Racine, E., Vollmann, J., and Schildmann, J. (2013). How research on stakeholder perspectives can inform policy on cognitive enhancement. AJOB 13, 41–43. doi: 10. 1080/15265161. 2013. 794882

||

Forsberg, L. (2013). “ No pain, no gain? Objections to the use of cognitive enhancement on the basis of its potential effects on the value of achievement,” in Cognitive Enhancement: An Interdisciplinary Perspective , eds E. Hildt and A. G. Franke (Dordrecht: Springer), 159–171.

Franke, A. G., Bagusat, C., Dietz, P., Hoffmann, I., Simon, P., Ulrich, R., et al. (2013). Use of illicit and prescription drugs for cognitive or mood enhancement among surgeons. BMC Med. 11: 102. doi: 10. 1186/1741-7015-11-102

||

Fukuyama, F. (2002). Our Posthuman Future: Consequences of the Biotechnology Revolution. New York, NY: Profile Books.

Gazzaniga, M. S. (2006). The Ethical Brain: The Science of Our Moral Dilemmas, Reprint Edition. New York, NY: Harper Perennial.

Goodman, R. (2010). Cognitive enhancement, cheating, and accomplishment. Kennedy Inst. Ethics J. 20, 145–160. doi: 10. 1353/ken. 0. 0309

||

Goold, I., and Maslen, H. (2014). Must the surgeon take the pill? negligence duty in the context of cognitive enhancement. Mod. Law. Rev. 77, 60–86. doi: 10. 1111/1468-2230. 12056

|

Greely, H., Sahakian, B. J., Harris, J., Kessler, R. C., Gazzaniga, M., Campbell, P., et al. (2008). Towards responsible use of cognitive enhancing drugs by the healthy. Nature 456, 702–705. doi: 10. 1038/456702a

||

Harris, J. (2012). What It’s Like to Be Good. Camb. Q. Healthc. Ethic. 21, 293–305. doi: 10. 1017/S0963180111000867

||

Hildt, E., and Franke, A. G. (2013). Cognitive Enhancement: An Interdisciplinary Perspective. Dordrecht: Springer.

Hursthouse, R. (1991). “ Virtue theory and abortion,” in Philosophy & Public Affairs , Vol. 20, (New York, NY: Wiley), 223–246. Available at:

Husain, M., and Mehta, M. A. (2011). Cognitive enhancement by drugs in health and disease. Trends Cogn. Sci. 15, 28–36. doi: 10. 1016/j. tics. 2010. 11. 002

||

Ilieva, I., Boland, J., and Farah, M. J. (2013). Objective and subjective cognitive enhancing effects of mixed amphetamine salts in healthy people. Neuropharmacology 64, 496–505. doi: 10. 1016/j. neuropharm. 2012. 07. 021

||

Ilieva, I. P., Hook, C. J., and Farah, M. J. (2015). Prescription stimulants’ effects on healthy inhibitory control, working memory, and episodic memory: a meta-analysis. J. Cogn. Neurosci. 27, 1069–1089. doi: 10. 1162/jocn_a_00776

||

Juengst, E. (2000). “ What does enhancement mean?,” in Enhancing Human Traits: Ethical and Social Implications , ed. E. Parens (Washington, DC: Georgetown University Press), 29–47.

Kagan, S. (2012). The Geometry of Desert. New York, NY: Oxford University Press.

Kant, I. (1786/2013). Grundlegung zur Metaphysik der Sitten . Riga: Johann Friedrich Harknoch.

Kass, L. R. (2003). Ageless bodies, happy souls. New Atlantis 1, 9–28.

|

Lenk, C. (2007). Is enhancement in sport really unfair? Arguments on the concept of competition and equality of opportunities. Sport Ethics Philos. 1, 218–228. doi: 10. 1080/17511320701425157

|

Little, M. O. (1998). “ Cosmetic surgery, suspect norms, and the ethics of complicity,” in Enhancing Human Traits: Ethical and Social Implications , ed. E. Parens (Washington, DC: Georgetown University Press), 162–176.

Maher, B. (2008). Poll results: look who’s doping. Nature 452, 674–675. doi: 10. 1038/452674a

||

Maier, L. J., Haug, S., and Schaub, M. P. (2015). Prevalence of and motives for pharmacological neuroenhancement in Switzerland—results from a national internet panel. Addiction 111, 280–295. doi: 10. 1111/add. 13059

||

Maslen, H., Santoni de Sio, F., and Faber, N. S. (2015). “ With cognitive enhancement comes great responsibility?,” in Responsible Innovation 2 – Concepts, Approaches, and Applications , eds B.-J. Koops, I. Oosterlaken, H. Romijn, T. Swierstra, and J. van den Hoven (Cham: Springer International Publishing), 121–138.

Maslen, H., Douglas, T., Kadosh, R. C., Levy, N., and Savulescu, J. (2014a). The regulation of cognitive enhancement devices: extending the medical model. J. Law Biosci. 1, 68–93. doi: 10. 1093/jlb/lst003

||

Maslen, H., Faulmüller, N., and Savulescu, J. (2014b). Pharmacological cognitive enhancement – How neuroscientific research could advance ethical debate. Front. Syst. Neurosci. 8: 107. doi: 10. 3389/fnsys. 2014. 00107

|

Mehlman, M. J. (2004). Cognition-enhancing drugs. Milbank Q. 82, 483–506. doi: 10. 1111/j. 0887-378X. 2004. 00319. x

||

Milne, H. (1986). Desert, effort and equality. J. Appl. Philos. 3, 235–243. doi: 10. 1111/j. 1468-5930. 1986. tb00423. x

|

Repantis, D., Schlattmann, P., Laisney, O., and Heuser, I. (2010). Modafinil and methylphenidate for neuroenhancement in healthy individuals: a systematic review. Pharmacol. Res. 62, 187–206. doi: 10. 1016/j. phrs. 2010. 04. 002

||

Roache, R. (2008). Enhancement and cheating. Expositions 2, 153–156. doi: 10. 1558/expo. v2i2. 153

|

Rose, S. (2006). The Future of the Brain: The Promise and Perils of Tomorrow’s Neuroscience. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

Rucker, D. R., McShane, B. B., and Preacher, K. J. (2015). A researcher’s guide to regression, discretization, and median splits of continuous variables. J. Consum. Psychol. 25, 666–678. doi: 10. 1016/j. jcps. 2015. 04. 004

|

Sadurski, W. (1985). Giving Desert Its Due: Social Justice and Legal Theory. Berlin: Springer Science & Business Media.

Sahakian, B. J., Bruhl, A. B., Cook, J., Killikelly, C., Savulich, G., Piercy, T., et al. (2015). The impact of neuroscience on society: cognitive enhancement in neuropsychiatric disorders and in healthy people. Philos. Trans. R. Soc. B. 370: 20140214. doi: 10. 1098/rstb. 2014. 0214

||

Sandel, M. (2007). The Case Against Perfection: Ethics in the Age of Genetic Engineering. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

Santoni de Sio, F., Faber, N. S., Savulescu, J., and Vincent, N. A. (in press). “ Why less praise for enhanced performance? Moving beyond responsibility-shifting, authenticity, and cheating, towards a nature-of-activities approach,” in Cognitive Enhancement: Ethical and Policy Implications in International Perspectives , eds F. Jotterand and V. Dubljevic (Oxford: Oxford University Press).

Santoni de Sio, F., Faulmüller, N., and Vincent, N. A. (2014). How cognitive enhancement can change our duties. Front. Syst. Neurosci. 8: 131. doi: 10. 3389/fnsys. 2014. 00131

||

Sattler, S., Forlini, C., Racine, E., and Sauer, C. (2013). Impact of contextual factors and substance characteristics on perspectives toward cognitive enhancement. PLoS ONE 8: e71452. doi: 10. 1371/journal. pone. 0071452

||

Savulescu, J. (2006). Justice, fairness, and enhancement. Ann. NY Acad. Sci. 1093, 321–338. doi: 10. 1196/annals. 1382. 021

||

Savulescu, J. (2009). “ Genetic enhancement,” in A Companion to Bioethics , 2nd Edn, eds H. Kuhse and P. Singer (Oxford: Wiley- Blackwell), 216–234.

Savulescu, J. (2015). “ Healthy why we should legalise performance-enhancing drugs in sport,” in Routledge Handbook of Drugs and Sport , eds V. Møller, I. Waddington, and J. M. Hoberman (London: Routledge).

Schelle, K. J., Faulmüller, N., Caviola, L., and Hewstone, M. (2014). Attitudes towards pharmacological cognitive enhancement – a review. Front. Syst. Neurosci. 8: 53. doi: 10. 3389/fnsys. 2014. 00053

|

Schelle, K. J., Olthof, B. M. J., Reintjes, W., Bundt, C., Gusman-Vermeer, J., and van Mil, A. C. C. M. (2015). A survey of substance use for cognitive enhancement by university students in the Netherlands. Front. Syst. Neurosci. 9: 10. doi: 10. 3389/fnsys. 2015. 00010

||

Schermer, M. (2008). On the argument that enhancement is “ cheating. J. Med. Ethics 34, 85–88. doi: 10. 1136/jme. 2006. 019646

||

Schermer, M., Bolt, I., De Jongh, R., and Olivier, B. (2009). The future of psychopharmacological enhancements: expectations and policies. Neuroethics 2, 75–87. doi: 10. 1007/s12152-009-9032-1

|

Scheske, C., and Schnall, S. (2012). The ethics of ‘ smart drugs’: moral judgments about healthy people’s use of cognitive-enhancing drugs. Basic Appl. Soc. Psychol. 34, 508–515. doi: 10. 1080/01973533. 2012. 711692

|

Sidgwick, H. (1893). The Methods of Ethics , 5th Edn. London: Macmillan and Co.

Singh, I., Bard, I., and Jackson, J. (2014). Robust resilience and substantial interest: a survey of pharmacological cognitive enhancement among university students in the UK and Ireland. PLoS ONE 9: e105969. doi: 10. 1371/journal. pone. 0105969

||

Sinnott-Armstrong, W. (2001). What is consequentialism? A reply to howard-snyder. Utilitas 13, 342–349. doi: 10. 1017/S0953820800003228

|

Skorupski, J. (1995). Agent-neutrality, consequentialism, utilitarianism a terminological note. Utilitas 7, 49–54. doi: 10. 1017/S0953820800001837

|

Smith, M. E., and Farah, M. J. (2011). Are prescription stimulants “ smart pills”? The epidemiology and cognitive neuroscience of prescription stimulant use by normal healthy individuals. Psychol. Bull. 137, 717–741. doi: 10. 1037/a0023825

||

Sorensen, K. (2010). Effort and moral worth. Ethical Theory Moral Pract. 13, 89–109. doi: 10. 1007/s10677-009-9159-5

|

Sparrow, R. (2014). Better living through chemistry? A reply to savulescu and persson on “ moral enhancement. J. Appl. Philos. 31, 23–32. doi: 10. 1111/japp. 12038

|

The President’s Council on Bioethics (U. S.) (2003). Beyond Therapy: Biotechnology and the Pursuit of Happiness. Washington, DC: President’s Council on Bioethics.

Turner, D. C., Robbins, T. W., Clark, L., Aron, A. R., Dowson, J., and Sahakian, B. J. (2003). Cognitive enhancing effects of modafinil in healthy volunteers. Psychopharmacology (Berl.) 165, 260–269. doi: 10. 1007/s00213-002-1250-8

||

Whitehouse, P. J., Juengst, E., Mehlman, M., and Murray, T. H. (1997). Enhancing cognition in the intellectually intact. Hast. Center Rep. 27, 14–22. doi: 10. 2307/3528662

||

Wiegel, C., Sattler, S., Göritz, A. S., and Diewald, M. (2015). Work-related stress and cognitive enhancement among university teachers. Anxiety Stress Coping 29, 100–117. doi: 10. 1080/10615806. 2015. 1025764

||

Wolff, W., and Brand, R. (2013). Subjective stressors in school and their relation to neuroenhancement: a behavioral perspective on students’ everyday life “ doping”. Subst. Abuse Treat. Prev. Policy 8: 23. doi: 10. 1186/1747-597X-8-23

||

Wolff, W., Brand, R., Baumgarten, F., Lösel, J., and Ziegler, M. (2014). Modeling students instrumental (mis-) use of substances to enhance cognitive performance: neuroenhancement in the light of job demands-resources theory. Biopsychosoc. Med. 8: 12. doi: 10. 1186/1751-0759-8-12

||

Thank's for Your Vote!
Why is cognitive enhancement deemed unacceptable? the role of fairness, deservingness, and hollow achievements. Page 1
Why is cognitive enhancement deemed unacceptable? the role of fairness, deservingness, and hollow achievements. Page 2
Why is cognitive enhancement deemed unacceptable? the role of fairness, deservingness, and hollow achievements. Page 3
Why is cognitive enhancement deemed unacceptable? the role of fairness, deservingness, and hollow achievements. Page 4
Why is cognitive enhancement deemed unacceptable? the role of fairness, deservingness, and hollow achievements. Page 5
Why is cognitive enhancement deemed unacceptable? the role of fairness, deservingness, and hollow achievements. Page 6
Why is cognitive enhancement deemed unacceptable? the role of fairness, deservingness, and hollow achievements. Page 7
Why is cognitive enhancement deemed unacceptable? the role of fairness, deservingness, and hollow achievements. Page 8
Why is cognitive enhancement deemed unacceptable? the role of fairness, deservingness, and hollow achievements. Page 9

This work, titled "Why is cognitive enhancement deemed unacceptable? the role of fairness, deservingness, and hollow achievements" was written and willingly shared by a fellow student. This sample can be utilized as a research and reference resource to aid in the writing of your own work. Any use of the work that does not include an appropriate citation is banned.

If you are the owner of this work and don’t want it to be published on AssignBuster, request its removal.

Request Removal
Cite this Essay

References

AssignBuster. (2021) 'Why is cognitive enhancement deemed unacceptable? the role of fairness, deservingness, and hollow achievements'. 21 December.

Reference

AssignBuster. (2021, December 21). Why is cognitive enhancement deemed unacceptable? the role of fairness, deservingness, and hollow achievements. Retrieved from https://assignbuster.com/why-is-cognitive-enhancement-deemed-unacceptable-the-role-of-fairness-deservingness-and-hollow-achievements/

References

AssignBuster. 2021. "Why is cognitive enhancement deemed unacceptable? the role of fairness, deservingness, and hollow achievements." December 21, 2021. https://assignbuster.com/why-is-cognitive-enhancement-deemed-unacceptable-the-role-of-fairness-deservingness-and-hollow-achievements/.

1. AssignBuster. "Why is cognitive enhancement deemed unacceptable? the role of fairness, deservingness, and hollow achievements." December 21, 2021. https://assignbuster.com/why-is-cognitive-enhancement-deemed-unacceptable-the-role-of-fairness-deservingness-and-hollow-achievements/.


Bibliography


AssignBuster. "Why is cognitive enhancement deemed unacceptable? the role of fairness, deservingness, and hollow achievements." December 21, 2021. https://assignbuster.com/why-is-cognitive-enhancement-deemed-unacceptable-the-role-of-fairness-deservingness-and-hollow-achievements/.

Work Cited

"Why is cognitive enhancement deemed unacceptable? the role of fairness, deservingness, and hollow achievements." AssignBuster, 21 Dec. 2021, assignbuster.com/why-is-cognitive-enhancement-deemed-unacceptable-the-role-of-fairness-deservingness-and-hollow-achievements/.

Get in Touch

Please, let us know if you have any ideas on improving Why is cognitive enhancement deemed unacceptable? the role of fairness, deservingness, and hollow achievements, or our service. We will be happy to hear what you think: [email protected]