1,842
9
Essay, 18 pages (4500 words)

Romeo and juliet random notes essay

Patriarch’s descriptions of Laura are lofty, flowery, and even exaggerated. Courtly love – the medieval tradition of love between a knight and a noble woman, characterized by chivalry, flowery praise, and a lack of any real contact/consummation Patriarch Born Francesco Footrace in Tuscany (Italy) in 1304. He grew up in a fairly wealthy family and was forced by his parents to study law, though his real interests were poetry and Latin literature. He was a prolific writer, traveler, and translator/discover-ere of ancient Roman and Greek manuscripts – laid the groundwork for the Renaissance In his dialogueThe Symposium, Plato has Aristotelian present a story about soul mates. Aristotelian states that humans originally had four arms, four legs, and a single head made of two faces. He continues that there were three genders: man, woman and the “ androgynous”. Each with two sets of genitalia with the Androgynous having both male and female genitalia.

The men were children of the sun, the women were children of the earth and the Androgynous were children of the moon, which was born of the sun and earth. It is said that humans had great strength at the time and threatened to conquer the gods. The gods were then faced with the prospect of destroying the humans with lightning as they had done with the Titans but then they would lose the tributes given to the gods by humans.

Zeus developed a creative solution by splitting humans in half as punishment for humanity’s pride and doubling the number of humans who would give tribute to the gods. These split humans were in utter misery to the point where they would not eat and would perish so Apollo had sewn them up and reconstituted their bodies with the navel being the only remnant hardening back to their original form. Each human old then only have one set of genitalia and would forever long for his/her other half; the other half of his/her soul.

It is said that when the two find each other, there is an unspoken understanding of one another, that they feel unified and would lay with each other in unity and would know no greater joy than that According to Theosophy, whose claims were modified by Edgar Jaycee, God created androgynous souls-? equally male and female. Later theories postulate that the souls split into separate genders, perhaps because they incurred karma while playing around on the Earth, or “ separation from God. Over a number Of reincarnations, each half seeks the other. When all karmic debt is purged, the two will fuse back together and return to the ultimate. Current usage of the concept In current usage, “ osculate” usually refers to a romantic partner, with the implication of an exclusive lifelong bond. [J This is to say, the word is used with more rarity than the terms also associated with ‘ romantic partner’. The term is a very versatile term, being defined differently by different individuals, as it is related to the concept of love.

It commonly holds the connotation of being the strongest bond with another romantically, that one can achieve. The term is not used as often as other terms representing the same idea, and this is likely to lead to its perceived rarity in meaning. The definition of it ranges widely, and cannot be pinpointed. It is commonly accepted that one will feel ; complete’ once they have found their soul mate, as it is partially in the perceived definition that two souls are meant to unite. Discuss the different types of love shown in the play Romeo and Juliet In the play Romeo and Juliet many different types of love are shown.

Love is displayed in many ways through friendship family and the love you have for a girlfriend or boyfriend. The first and probably most well known type of love is the passionate sexual and romantic love that is shown by the characters Romeo and Juliet. This type of love is unconditional and lasts forever as Romeo and Juliet would rather die than be without each other.

Ironically Romeo and Gullet’s love is everlasting as they have not had enough time to find faults with each other or to start to dislike one another’s qualities in any way. They are still very much in love with each other on the day they die and so there was no time for their love to fade. Throughout the whole play, there are constant reminders to the audience owe very much in love Romeo and Juliet are with each other. They are reminded how very much Romeo values Juliet as he is constantly referring to her as the light in darkness, that The concept of fate functions as a central theme in Shakespearean Romeo and Juliet.

In the opening prologue of the play, the Chorus informs the audience that Romeo and Juliet are “ Star h cross’s Lovers” (Prologue 1. 6). In other words, the Chorus states that Romeo and Juliet are governed by fate, a force often linked to the movements of the stars. Fate manifests itself in all the events surrounding the young lovers: the ancient and inexplicable feud teen their families, the catastrophic series of mishaps which ruin Friar Lawrence plans, and the tragic timing of Romeos suicide and Gullet’s awakening. The structure of the play itself rests upon the fate from which the two lovers cannot escape. The play opens with a brawl which erupts between servants of the Montague and Caplet families. This initial quarrel illustrates that the “ ancient Grudge” between the two families runs so deep that it extends to the servants (Prologue l.

). Upon their first encounter, Romeo and Juliet remain ignorant to the fact that they are the children of feuding families. Actually, the lovers et by coincidence. Romeo agrees to attend the Caplet ball because he hopes to see Rosalie, and he n this essay I will concentrate on the love aspect in one of William Shakespearean most popular tragedies, written during the 16th century – Romeo and Juliet. This essay will mainly concentrate on three key scenes and these are as follows -Act 1 Sc 5; Act 2 Sc 2 and Act 3 Sc 5. In these scenes will show how Shakespeare portrays the love aspect in Romeo and Juliet – and in these scenes it is shown in a clear, clever and coherent way. Shakespeare shows this cleverly by the use of stage-craft and dramatic irony to show clear organization of characters on stage when the play is being acted to a large number of audience.

Even the structure in which the scenes are organized can be interpreted, noticed and referred to by the audience as the play graduates. Not only this; the ingenious linguistic features that Shakespeare uses can be used to show tension, tidiness, love and even happiness. In Romeo and Juliet, love is a violent, ecstatic, overpowering force that supersedes all other values, loyalties, and emotions. (Bookmarks. Com) In the course of the play, the romantic lovers are driven to defy their entire social world. Juliet says once to Romeo, “ Deny thy father and refuse thy name, Or if thou wilt not, be but sworn my love, And I’ll no longer be a Caplet.

” (Act II, Scene ii, Lines 37-39) This is just one of the countless times she goes behind her family’s back to meet with someone of the other house. Hilltop’s of Love: An Overview This article examines the nature of love and some of the ethical and political ramifications. For the philosopher, the question ‘ Whap is love? ” generates a host of issues: love is an abstract noun which means for some it is a word unattached to anything real or sensible, that is all; for others, it is a means by which our being – our self and its world – are irrevocably affected once we are ‘ touched by love’; some have sought to analyze it, others have preferred to leave it in the realm of the ineffable. Yet it is undeniable that love plays an enormous and unavoidable role in our several cultures; we find it discussed in song, film, and novels – humorously or seriously; it is a constant theme of maturing life and a vibrant theme for youth. Philosophically, the nature of love has, since the time of the Ancient Greeks, been a mainstay in philosophy, producing theories that range from the materialistic conception of love as rely a physical phenomenon -? an annalistic or genetic urge that dictates our behavior – to theories of love as an intensely spiritual affair that in its highest permits us to touch divinity. Historically, in the Western tradition, Plat’s Symposium presents the initiating text, for it provides us with an enormously influential and attractive notion that love is characterized by a series of elevations, in which annalistic desire or base lust is superseded by a more intellectual conception of love which also is surpassed by what may be construed by a theological vision of love that transcends sensual attraction ND mutuality.

Since then there have been detractors and supporters of Platonic love as well as a host of alternative theories – including that of Plat’s student, Aristotle and his more secular theory of true love reflecting what he described as two bodies and one soul. ‘ The philosophical treatment Of love transcends a variety of sub-disciplines including epistemology, metaphysics, religion, human nature, politics and ethics. Often statements or arguments concerning love, its nature and role in human life for example connect to one or all the central theories of philosophy, and is often compared with, or examined in the context of, the philosophies of sex and gender as well as body and intentionality. The task of a philosophy of love is to present the appropriate issues in a cogent manner, drawing on relevant theories of human nature, desire, ethics, and so on.

1 The Nature of Love: Eros, Philip, and Agape The philosophical discussion regarding love logically begins with questions concerning its nature. This implies that love has a “ nature,” a proposition that some may oppose arguing that love is conceptually irrational, in the sense that it cannot be described in rational or meaningful propositions. For such critics, who are presenting a metaphysical and epistemological argument, love may be an ejection of emotions that defy rational examination; on the other hand, some languages, such as Paean, do not even admit the concept, which negates the possibility of a philosophical examination. In English, the word “ love,” which is derived from Germanic forms of the Sanskrit lube (desire), is broadly defined and hence imprecise, which generates first order problems of definition and meaning which are resolved to some extent by the reference to the Greek terms, Eros, Philip, and agape.

A. Eros The term Eros (Greek reassert) is used to refer to that part of love constituting a passionate, intense desire for something; it is often referred to as a sexual desire, hence the modern notion of “ erotic” (Greek erotic). In Plat’s writings however, Eros is held to be a common desire that seeks transcendental beauty-the particular beauty of an individual reminds us of true beauty that exists in the world of Forms or Ideas (Phaedra IEEE: “ he who loves the beautiful is called a lover because he partakes of it.

” Trans. Jowett). The Platonic-Socratic position maintains that the love we generate for tatty on this earth can never be truly satisfied until we die; but in the meantime we should aspire beyond the particular stimulating image in front of us to the contemplation of beauty in itself. The implication of the Platonic theory of Eros is that ideal beauty, which is reflected in the particular images of beauty we find, becomes interchangeable across people and things, ideas, and art: to love is to love the Platonic form of beauty-not a particular individual, but the element they posses of true (Ideal) beauty. Reciprocity is not necessary to Plat’s view of love, for the desire is for the object (of Beauty), than for, say, the company of another and shared values and pursuits. Many in the Platonic vein of philosophy hold that love is an intrinsically higher value than appetitive or physical desire. Physical desire, they note, is held in common with the animal kingdom. Hence, it is of a lower order of reaction and stimulus than a rationally induced love-? that is, a love produced by rational discourse and exploration of ideas, which in turn defines the pursuit of Ideal beauty.

Accordingly, the physical love of an object, an idea, or a person in itself is not a proper form of love, love being a affliction of that part of the object, idea, or person, that partakes in Ideal beauty. . Philip In contrast to the desiring and passionate yearning of Eros, phi Lila entails a fondness and appreciation of the other. For the Greeks, the term Philip incorporated notes friendship, but also loyalties to family and polis-one’s political community, job, or discipline. Philip for another may be motivated, as Aristotle explains in the Mechanical Ethics, Book VIII, for the agent’s sake or for the other’s own sake. The motivational distinctions are derived from love for another because the friendship is wholly useful as in the case of business intact, or because their character and values are pleasing (with the implication that if those attractive habits change, so too does the friendship), or for the other in who they are in themselves, regardless of one’s interests in the matter. The English concept of friendship roughly captures Aristotle notion of Philip, as he writes: “ things that cause friendship are: doing kindnesses; doing them unasked; and not proclaiming the fact when they are done” (Rhetoric, II.

4, trans. Rays Roberts). Aristotle elaborates on the kinds of things we seek in proper friendship, suggesting that the proper basis for hill is objective: those who share our dispositions, who bear no grudges, who seek what we do, who are temperate, and just, who admire us appropriately as we admire them, and so on. Philip could not emanate from those who are quarrelsome, gossips, aggressive in manner and personality, who are unjust, and so on. The best characters, it follows, may produce the best kind of friendship and hence love: indeed, how to be a good character worthy of Philip is the theme of the Monomaniacs Ethics. The most rational man is he who would be the happiest, and he, therefore, who is capable of he best form of friendship, which between two “ who are good, and alike in virtue” is rare (EN, VIII.

4 trans. Ross). We can surmise that love between such equals-Aristotle rational and happy men-would be perfect, with circles of diminishing quality for those who are morally removed from the best. He characterizes such love as “ a sort of excess of feeling”. (EN, VIII. 6) Friendships of a lesser quality may also be based on the pleasure or utility that is derived from another’s company.

A business friendship is based on utility-on mutual reciprocity of similar business interests; once the business is at an end, then he friendship dissolves. This is similar to those friendships based on the pleasure that is derived from the other’s company, which is not a pleasure enjoyed for whom the other person is in himself, but in the flow of pleasure from his actions or humor. The first condition for the highest form of Aristotelian love is that a man loves himself. Without an egoistic basis, he cannot extend sympathy and affection to others (EN, IX. 8). Such self-love is not hedonistic, or glorified, depending on the pursuit of immediate pleasures or the adulation of the crowd, it is instead a reflection Of his pursuit of the bole and virtuous, which culminate in the pursuit of the reflective life. Friendship with others is required “ since his purpose is to contemplate worthy actions.

.. To live pleasantly… Sharing in discussion and thought” as is appropriate for the virtuous man and his friend (EN, IX.

9). The morally virtuous man deserves in turn the love of those below him; he is not obliged to give an equal love in return, which implies that the Aristotelian concept of love is elitist or perfectionist: “ In all friendships implying inequality the love also should be proportional, I. E.

The better should be more loved than he eves. ” (EN, VIII, 7,). Reciprocity, although not necessarily equal, is a condition of Aristotelian love and friendship, although parental love can involve a one- sided fondness. C. Agape Agape refers to the paternal love of God for man and of man for God but is extended to include a brotherly love for all humanity. The Hebrew behave has a slightly wider semantic range than agape). Agape arguably draws on elements from both Eros and Philip in that it seeks a perfect kind of love that is at once a fondness, a transcending of the particular, and a passion without the necessity of reciprocity. The concept is expanded on in the Judaic-Christian tradition of loving God: ‘ ‘ You shall love the Lord your God with all your heart, and with all your soul, and with all your might” (Deuteron 6: 5) and loving “ thy neighbor as thyself’ (Leviticus 1 9: 18).

The love of God requires absolute devotion that is reminiscent of Plat’s love of Beauty (and Christian translators of Plato such as SST. Augustine employed the connections), which involves an erotic passion, awe, and desire that transcends earthly cares and obstacles. Aquinas, on the other hand, picked up on the Aristotelian theories f friendship and love to proclaim God as the most rational being and hence the most deserving of one’s love, respect, and considerations.

The universalism command to “ love thy neighbor as thyself’ refers the subject to those surrounding him, whom he should love unilaterally if necessary. The command employs the logic of mutual reciprocity, and hints at an Aristotelian basis that the subject should love himself in some appropriate manner: for awkward results would ensue if he loved himself in a particularly inappropriate, perverted manner! (Philosophers can debate the nature of self-love” implied in this-from the Aristotelian notion that self-love is necessary for any kind of interpersonal love, to the condemnation of egoism and the impoverished examples that pride and self-glorification from which to base one’s love of another. SST. Augustine relinquishes the debate-he claims that no command is needed for a man to love himself (De bono vitiates, xix.

) Analogous to the logic of “ it is better to give than to receive”, the universalism of agape requires an initial invocation from someone: in a reversal of the Aristotelian position, the onus for the Christian is on the orally superior to extend love to others. Nonetheless, the command also entails an egalitarian love-hence the Christian code to “ love thy enemies” (Matthew 5: 44-45). Such love transcends any perfectionist or aristocratic notions that some are (or should be) more lovable than others. Agape finds echoes in the ethics of Kant and Segregated, who assert the moral importance of giving impartial respect or love to another person qua human being in the abstract. However, loving one’s neighbor impartially (James 2: 9) invokes serious ethical concerns, especially if the neighbor ostensibly does not warrant love. Debate thus begins on what elements of a neighbor’s conduct should be included in agape, and which should be excluded.

Early Christians asked whether the principle applied only to disciples of Christ or to all. The imperialists won the debate asserting that the neighbor’s humanity provides the primary condition of being loved; nonetheless his actions may require a second order of criticisms, for the logic of brotherly love implies that it is a moral improvement on brotherly hate. For metaphysical dualist, loving the soul rather than the neighbor’s body or deeds provides a useful escape luaus-or in turn the justification for penalizing the other’s body for sin and moral transgressions, while releasing the proper object of love-the soul-from its secular torments. For Christian pacifists, ‘ turning the other cheek” to aggression and violence implies a hope that the aggressor will eventually learn to comprehend the higher values of peace, forgiveness, and a love for humanity. The universalism of agape runs counter to the partiality of Aristotle and poses a variety of ethical implications. Aquinas admits a partiality in love towards those we are related while maintaining that we would be charitable to all, whereas others such as Segregated insist on impartiality. Recently, Hugh Lafayette (1991) has noted that to love those one is partial towards is not necessarily a negation Of the impartiality principle, for impartiality could admit loving those closer to one as an impartial principle, and, employing Aristotle conception of self-love, iterates that loving others requires an intimacy that can only be gained from being partially intimate. Others would claim that the concept of universal love, of loving all equally, is not only impracticable, but logically empty-Aristotle, for example, argues: One cannot be a friend to many people in the sense of having friendship of the perfect type with them, just as one cannot be in love with many people at once (for love is a sort of excess of feeling, and it is the nature of such only to be felt towards one person)” (EN, VIII.

6). 2. The Nature of Love: Further Conceptual Considerations Presuming love has a nature, it should be, to some extent at least, describable within the concepts of language. But what is meant by an appropriate language of description may be as philosophically beguiling as love itself. Such considerations invoke the philosophy of language, of the elevate and appropriateness of meanings, but they also provide the analysis of “ love” with its first principles. Does it exist and if so, is it knowable, comprehensible, and describable? Love may be knowable and comprehensible to others, as understood in the phrases, “ I am in love”, “ l love you”, but what “ love” means in these sentences may not be analyzed further: that is, the concept “ love” is irreducible-an axiomatic, or self-evident, state of affairs that warrants no further intellectual intrusion, an patriotic category perhaps, that a Kantian may recognize.

The epistemology of love asks how we ay know love, how we may understand it, whether it is possible or plausible to make statements about others or ourselves being in love (which touches on the philosophical issue of private knowledge versus public behavior). Again, the epistemology of love is intimately connected to the philosophy of language and theories of the emotions. If love is purely an emotional condition, it IS plausible to argue that It remains a private phenomenon incapable of being accessed by others, except through an expression of language, and language may be a poor indicator of an emotional state both or the listener and the subject. Motivates would hold that a statement such as “ l am in love” is irreducible to other statements because it is a nonprofessional utterance, hence its veracity is beyond examination. Phenomenological may similarly present love as a non-cognitive phenomenon. Schuler, for example, toys with Plat’s Ideal love, which is cognitive, claiming: “ love itself..

. Brings about the continuous emergence of ever-higher value in the object-just as if it were streaming out from the object of its own accord, without any exertion (even of wishing) on the part of the over” (1954, p. 57). The lover is passive before the beloved.

The claim that “ love” cannot be examined is different from that claiming “ love” should not be subject to examination-that it should be put or left beyond the mind’s reach, out of a dutiful respect for its mysteriousness, its awesome, divine, or romantic nature. But if it is agreed that there is such a thing as “ love” conceptually speaking, when people present statements concerning love, or admonitions such as “ she should show more love,” then a philosophical examination seems appropriate: is it synonymous with certain patterns of behavior, of inflections in the voice or manner, or by the apparent pursuit and protection of a particular value (“ Look at how he dotes upon his flowers-he must love them”)? If love does possesses “ a nature” which is identifiable by some means-a personal expression, a discernible pattern of behavior, or other activity, it can still be asked whether that nature can be properly understood by humanity. Love may have a nature, yet we may not possess the proper intellectual capacity to understand it-accordingly, we may gain glimpses perhaps of its essence-as Socrates argues in The Symposium, but its rue nature being forever beyond humanity’s intellectual grasp. Accordingly, love may be partially described, or hinted at, in a dialectic or analytical exposition of the concept but never understood in itself. Love may therefore become an epiphenomena entity, generated by human action in loving, but never grasped by the mind or language.

Love may be so described as a Platonic Form, belonging to the higher realm of transcendental concepts that mortals can barely conceive of in their purity, catching only glimpses of the Forms’ conceptual shadows that logic and reason unveil or disclose. Another IEEE, again derived from Platonic philosophy, may permit love to be understood by certain people and not others. This invokes a hierarchical epistemology, that only the initiated, the experienced, the philosophical, or the poetical or musical, may gain insights into its nature. On one level this admits that only the experienced can know its nature, which is putatively true of any experience, but it also may imply a social division of understanding- that only philosopher kings may know true love. On the first implication, those who do not feel or experience love are incapable (unless initiated wrought rite, dialectical philosophy, artistic processes, and so on) of comprehending its nature, whereas the second implication suggests (though this is not a logically necessary inference) that the non-initiated, or those incapable of understanding, feel only physical desire and not “ love. ” Accordingly, “ love” belongs either to the higher faculties of all, understanding of which requires being educated in some manner or form, or it belongs to the higher echelons of society-to a priestly, philosophical, or artistic, poetic class. The uninitiated, the incapable, or the young and inexperienced-those ho are not romantic troubadours-are doomed only to feel physical desire. This separating of love from physical desire has further implications concerning the nature of romantic love.

3. The Nature of Love: Romantic Love Romantic love is deemed to be of a higher metaphysical and ethical status than sexual or physical attractiveness alone. The idea of romantic love initially stems from the Platonic tradition that love is a desire for beauty-a value that transcends the particularities of the physical body. For Plato, the love of beauty culminates in the love of philosophy, the subject that pursues the sights capacity of thinking. The romantic love of knights and damsels emerged in the early medieval ages (1 lath Century France, fine amour) a philosophical echo of both Platonic and Aristotelian love and literally a derivative of the Roman poet, Ovid and his Ears Amatory. Romantic love theoretically was not to be consummated, for such love was transcendentally motivated by a deep respect for the lady; however, it was to be actively pursued in chivalric deeds rather than contemplated-which is in contrast to Ovoid’s persistent sensual pursuit of conquests! Modern romantic love returns o Aristotle version of the special love two people find in each others virtues-one soul and two bodies, as he poetically puts it. It is deemed to be of a higher status, ethically, aesthetically, and even metaphysically than the love that behaviorist’s or physicality describe. 4.

The Nature of Love: Physical, Emotional, Spiritual Some may hold that love is physical, I. E. , that love is nothing but a physical response to another whom the agent feels physically attracted to.

Accordingly, the action of loving encompasses a broad range of behavior including caring, listening, attending to, preferring to others, and so on. This would be proposed by behaviorist’s). Others (physicality, geneticists) reduce all examinations of love to the physical motivation Of the sexual impulse-the simple sexual instinct that is shared with all complex living entities, which may, in humans, be directed consciously, sub-consciously or pre-rationally toward a potential mate or object of sexual gratification. Physical determinist, those who believe the world to entirely physical and that every event has a prior (physical cause), consider love to be an extension of the chemical-biological constituents of the human creature and be explicable according to such processes.

In this vein, geneticists may invoke the theory that the genes (an individual’s DNA) form the determining criteria in any sexual or putative romantic choice, especially in choosing a mate. However, a problem for those who claim that love is reducible to the physical attractiveness of a potential mate, or to the blood ties of family and kin which forge bonds of filial love, is that it does not capture the affections between those who cannot or wish not to reproduce-that is, physicality or determinism ignores the possibility of romantic, additional love-? it may explain Eros, but not Philip or agape.

Thank's for Your Vote!
Romeo and juliet random notes essay. Page 1
Romeo and juliet random notes essay. Page 2
Romeo and juliet random notes essay. Page 3
Romeo and juliet random notes essay. Page 4
Romeo and juliet random notes essay. Page 5
Romeo and juliet random notes essay. Page 6
Romeo and juliet random notes essay. Page 7
Romeo and juliet random notes essay. Page 8
Romeo and juliet random notes essay. Page 9

This work, titled "Romeo and juliet random notes essay" was written and willingly shared by a fellow student. This sample can be utilized as a research and reference resource to aid in the writing of your own work. Any use of the work that does not include an appropriate citation is banned.

If you are the owner of this work and don’t want it to be published on AssignBuster, request its removal.

Request Removal
Cite this Essay

References

AssignBuster. (2021) 'Romeo and juliet random notes essay'. 19 December.

Reference

AssignBuster. (2021, December 19). Romeo and juliet random notes essay. Retrieved from https://assignbuster.com/romeo-and-juliet-random-notes-essay/

References

AssignBuster. 2021. "Romeo and juliet random notes essay." December 19, 2021. https://assignbuster.com/romeo-and-juliet-random-notes-essay/.

1. AssignBuster. "Romeo and juliet random notes essay." December 19, 2021. https://assignbuster.com/romeo-and-juliet-random-notes-essay/.


Bibliography


AssignBuster. "Romeo and juliet random notes essay." December 19, 2021. https://assignbuster.com/romeo-and-juliet-random-notes-essay/.

Work Cited

"Romeo and juliet random notes essay." AssignBuster, 19 Dec. 2021, assignbuster.com/romeo-and-juliet-random-notes-essay/.

Get in Touch

Please, let us know if you have any ideas on improving Romeo and juliet random notes essay, or our service. We will be happy to hear what you think: [email protected]