1,667
23
Thesis, 7 pages (1600 words)

Commentary: the need for bayesian hypothesis testing in psychological science

A commentary on
The Need for Bayesian Hypothesis Testing in Psychological Science

by Wagenmakers, E. J., Verhagen, J., Ly, A., Matzke, D., Steingroever, H., Rouder, J. N., et al. (2017). Psychological Science Under Scrutiny: Recent Challenges and Proposed Solutions, eds S. O. Lilienfeld and I. D. Waldman (Chichester: JohnWiley & Sons), 123–138..

Wagenmakers et al. (2017) argued the need for a Bayesian approach to inferential statistics in Psychological Science under Scrutiny . Their primary goal was to demonstrate the illogical nature of p -values, while, secondarily, they would also defend the philosophical consistency of the Bayesian alternative. In my opinion, they achieved their secondary goal but failed their primary one, thereby this contribution. I will, thus, comment on their interpretation of the logic underlying p -values without necessarily invalidating their Bayesian arguments.

Historical criticisms (e. g., Harshbarger, 1977 , onwards) have already delved in the illogical nature of null hypothesis significance testing (NHST)—a mishmash of Fisher’s, Neyman-Pearson’s, and Bayes’s ideas (e. g., Gigerenzer, 2004 ; Perezgonzalez, 2015a ). Wagenmakers et al.’s original contribution is to generalize similar criticisms to the p -value itself, the statistic used by frequentists when testing research data.

Wagenmakers et al. assert that Fisher’s disjunction upon obtaining a significant result—i. e., either a rare event occurred or H 0 is not true ( Fisher, 1959 )—follows from a logically consistent modus tollens (also Sober, 2008 ): If P, then Q; not Q; therefore not P, which the authors parsed as, If H 0 , then not y; y; therefore not H 0 .

“ Y” is defined as “ the observed data…[summarized by] the p -value” (p. 126). Therefore, their first premise proposes that, if H 0 is true, the observed p -values cannot occur (also Cohen, 1994 ; Beck-Bornholdt and Dubben, 1996 ). This seems incongruent, as the first premise of a correct modus tollens states a general rule—H 0 implies “ not y”—while the second premise states a specific test to such rule—“ this y” has been observed. If the authors meant for “ y” to represent “ significant data” as a general category in the first premise and as a specific realization in the second, a congruent modus tollens would ensue, as follows (also Pollard and Richardson, 1987 ):

If H 0 , then not p < sig; p < sig (observed); therefore not H 0 (1)

Wagenmakers et al.’s (also Pollard and Richardson, 1987 ; Cohen, 1994 ; Falk, 1998 ) main argument is that a correct modus tollens is rendered inconsistent when made probabilistic, as follows:

If H 0 , then p < sig very unlikely; p < sig; therefore probably not H 0 (2)

There are, however, three problems with (2), problems which I would like to comment upon. One problem is stylistic: The first premise states a redundant probability; that is, that a significant result—which already implies an unlikely or improbable event under H 0 —is unlikely. Therefore, the syllogism could be simplified as follows:

If H 0 , then p < sig; p < sig; therefore probably not H 0 (3)

Correction (3) now highlights another of the problems: The second premise simply affirms that an unlikely result just happened (also Cortina and Dunlap, 1997 ), something which is neither precluded by the first premise (no contrapositive ensues; Adams, 1988 ) nor formally conducive to a logical conclusion under modus tollens ( Evans, 1982 ). Indeed, in the examples given (also by Cohen, 1994 ; Beck-Bornholdt and Dubben, 1996 ; Cortina and Dunlap, 1997 ; Krämer and Gigerenzer, 2005 ; Rouder et al., 2016 ), Tracy is a US congresswoman, Francis is the Pope, and John made money at the casino, each despite their odds against. Yet, none of those realizations deny the consequents. A correction, following Harshbarger (1977) and Falk (1998), would state:

If H 0 , then not p < sig; p < sig; therefore probably not H 0 (4)

Correction (4) brings to light the most important problem: Modus tollens is in the form, If P, then Q; not Q; therefore not P. Thus, whenever the consequent (Q) gets denied in the second premise, it leads to denying the antecedent (P) in the conclusion. Such operation ought to prevail with probabilistic premises, as well (e. g., Oaksford and Chater, 2001 , 2009 ; Evans et al., 2015 ), whereby a probable consequent (Q p ) may be denied without its probability warranting transposition onto a non-probabilistic antecedent (P). For example, if all red cars (P) have a 95% chance of getting stolen ( Q ≥ 0. 95) and we learn of a Lamborghini with a lesser probability of so disappearing (not Q ≥ 0. 95), it is logical to conclude that the Lamborghini is not red (not P).

In comparison, Bayesian logic allows for the antecedent to be probable. For example, if John always submits to Nature (Q) whenever his subjective probability of getting published soars above 20% ( P > 0. 2), yet he is not submitting his latest article (not Q), it is logical to conclude that he probably expects no publication (not P > 0. 2).

We can, thus, envisage P or Q, or both, as probable without either warranting inter-transposition of their probabilities, which brings us back to a valid modus tollens (1). Said otherwise, while Bayesian statistics allow for the antecedent to be probable (P p ), Fisher’s and Neyman-Pearson’s tests assume exact antecedents (P); therefore, a probabilistic conclusion does not hold with frequentist tests ( Mayo, 2017 ).

It ought to be noted that the p -value is a statistic descriptive of the probability of the data under H 0 [p(D| H 0 )] ( Perezgonzalez, 2015b ). The reductio ad absurdum argument may be informed by, but it is not dependent on, such p -value, the reductio being determined exclusively by the chosen level of significance. For “ it is open to the experimenter to be more or less exacting in respect of the smallness of the probability he would require before he would be willing to admit that his observations have demonstrated a positive result. It is obvious that an experiment would be useless of which no possible result would satisfy him” ( Fisher, 1960 , p. 13).

In conclusion, the technology of frequentist testing holds their modus tollens logically. Wagenmakers et al.’s criticism of the p -value is faulty in that they allow for a probability transposition not warranted either by modus tollens or by the technical apparatus of Fisher’s and of Neyman-Pearson’s tests. This critique, however, does not extend to their Bayesian argumentation, an approach much needed for testing hypotheses—rather than just testing data—in contemporary science.

Author Contributions

The author confirms being the sole contributor of this work and approved it for publication.

Conflict of Interest Statement

The author declares that the research was conducted in the absence of any commercial or financial relationships that could be construed as a potential conflict of interest.

References

Adams, E. W. (1988). Modus tollens revisited. Analysis 48, 122–128. doi: 10. 1093/analys/48. 3. 122

|

Beck-Bornholdt, H. P., and Dubben, H. H. (1996). Is the Pope an alien? Nature 381: 730. doi: 10. 1038/381730d0

Cohen, J. (1994). The earth is round (p < 0. 05). Am. Psychol. 49, 997–1003. doi: 10. 1037/0003-066X. 49. 12. 997

Cortina, J. M., and Dunlap, W. P. (1997). On the logic and purpose of significance testing. Psychol. Methods 2, 161–172. doi: 10. 1037/1082-989X. 2. 2. 161

|

Evans, J. St. B. T. (1982). The Psychology of Deductive Reasoning . London: Routledge & Kegan Paul.

Evans, J. St. B. T., Thompson, V. A., and Over, D. E. (2015). Uncertain deduction and conditional reasoning. Front. Psychol. 6: 398. doi: 10. 3389/fpsyg. 2015. 00398

|

Falk, R. (1998). In criticism of the null hypothesis statistical test. Am. Psychol. 53, 798–799. doi: 10. 1037/0003-066X. 53. 7. 798

Fisher, R. A. (1959). Statistical Methods and Scientific Inference, 2nd Edn . Edinburgh: Oliver and Boyd.

Fisher, R. A. (1960). The Design of Experiments, 7th Edn . Edinburgh: Oliver and Boyd.

Gigerenzer, G. (2004). Mindless statistics. J. Soc. Econ. 33, 587–606. doi: 10. 1016/j. socec. 2004. 09. 033

|

Harshbarger, T. R. (1977). Introductory Statistics: A Decision Map, 2nd Edn . New York, NY: Macmillan.

Krämer, W., and Gigerenzer, G. (2005). How to confuse with statistics or: the use of misuse of conditional probabilities. Stat. Sci. 20, 223–230. doi: 10. 1214/088342305000000296

|

Mayo, D. G. (2017). If You’re Seeing Limb-Sawing in p-value Logic, You’re Sawing off the Limbs of Reductio Arguments [Web Log Post]. Available online at:

Oaksford, M., and Chater, N. (2001). The probabilistic approach to human reasoning. Trends Cogn. Sci. 5, 349–357. doi: 10. 1016/S1364-6613(00)01699-5

|

Oaksford, M., and Chater, N. (2009). Précis of bayesian rationality: the probabilistic approach to human reasoning. Behav. Brain Sci. 32, 69–84. doi: 10. 1017/S0140525X09000284

|

Perezgonzalez, J. D. (2015a). Fisher, Neyman-Pearson or NHST? A tutorial for teaching data testing. Front. Psychol. 6: 223. doi: 10. 3389/fpsyg. 2015. 00223

||

Perezgonzalez, J. D. (2015b). P-values as percentiles. Commentary on: “ Null hypothesis significance tests. A mix–up of two different theories: the basis for widespread confusion and numerous misinterpretations.” Front. Psychol. 6: 341. doi: 10. 3389/fpsyg. 2015. 00341

|

Pollard, P., and Richardson, J. T. E. (1987). On the probability of making type I errors. Psychol. Bull. 102, 159–163. doi: 10. 1037/0033-2909. 102. 1. 159

|

Rouder, J. N., Morey, R. D., Verhagen, J., Province, J. M., and Wagenmakers, E. J. (2016). Is there a free lunch in inference? Top. Cogn. Sci. 8, 520–547. doi: 10. 1111/tops. 12214

|

Sober, E. (2008). Evidence and Evolution. The Logic Behind the Science . Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

Wagenmakers, E. J., Verhagen, J., Ly, A., Matzke, D., Steingroever, H., Rouder, J. N., et al. (2017). “ The need for Bayesian hypothesis testing in psychological science,” in Psychological Science under Scrutiny: Recent Challenges and Proposed Solutions , eds S. O. Lilienfeld and I. D. Waldman (Chichester: John Wiley & Sons), 123–138.

Thank's for Your Vote!
Commentary: the need for bayesian hypothesis testing in psychological science. Page 1
Commentary: the need for bayesian hypothesis testing in psychological science. Page 2
Commentary: the need for bayesian hypothesis testing in psychological science. Page 3
Commentary: the need for bayesian hypothesis testing in psychological science. Page 4
Commentary: the need for bayesian hypothesis testing in psychological science. Page 5
Commentary: the need for bayesian hypothesis testing in psychological science. Page 6
Commentary: the need for bayesian hypothesis testing in psychological science. Page 7
Commentary: the need for bayesian hypothesis testing in psychological science. Page 8
Commentary: the need for bayesian hypothesis testing in psychological science. Page 9

This work, titled "Commentary: the need for bayesian hypothesis testing in psychological science" was written and willingly shared by a fellow student. This sample can be utilized as a research and reference resource to aid in the writing of your own work. Any use of the work that does not include an appropriate citation is banned.

If you are the owner of this work and don’t want it to be published on AssignBuster, request its removal.

Request Removal
Cite this Thesis

References

AssignBuster. (2022) 'Commentary: the need for bayesian hypothesis testing in psychological science'. 29 July.

Reference

AssignBuster. (2022, July 29). Commentary: the need for bayesian hypothesis testing in psychological science. Retrieved from https://assignbuster.com/commentary-the-need-for-bayesian-hypothesis-testing-in-psychological-science/

References

AssignBuster. 2022. "Commentary: the need for bayesian hypothesis testing in psychological science." July 29, 2022. https://assignbuster.com/commentary-the-need-for-bayesian-hypothesis-testing-in-psychological-science/.

1. AssignBuster. "Commentary: the need for bayesian hypothesis testing in psychological science." July 29, 2022. https://assignbuster.com/commentary-the-need-for-bayesian-hypothesis-testing-in-psychological-science/.


Bibliography


AssignBuster. "Commentary: the need for bayesian hypothesis testing in psychological science." July 29, 2022. https://assignbuster.com/commentary-the-need-for-bayesian-hypothesis-testing-in-psychological-science/.

Work Cited

"Commentary: the need for bayesian hypothesis testing in psychological science." AssignBuster, 29 July 2022, assignbuster.com/commentary-the-need-for-bayesian-hypothesis-testing-in-psychological-science/.

Get in Touch

Please, let us know if you have any ideas on improving Commentary: the need for bayesian hypothesis testing in psychological science, or our service. We will be happy to hear what you think: [email protected]